Engels@200:
Friedrich
Engels and Digital Capitalism.
How Relevant Are Engels’s Works 200 Years After His Birth?
Christian Fuchs
University
of
Westminster, christian.fuchs@uti.at,
http://fuchs.uti.at,
@fuchschristian
Abstract: This paper takes Friedrich Engels 200th birthday on 28 November 2020 as occasion to ask: How relevant are Friedrich Engels’s works in the age of digital capitalism? It shows that Engels class-struggle oriented theory can and should inform 21st century social science and digital social research. Based on a reading of Engels’s works, the article discusses how to think of scientific socialism as critical social science today, presents a critique of computational social science as digital positivism, engages with foundations of digital labour analysis, the analysis of the international division of digital labour, updates Engels’s Condition of the Working Class in England in the age of digital capitalism, analyses the role of trade unions and digital class struggles in digital age, analyses the social murder of workers in the COVID-19 crisis, engages with platform co-operatives, digital commons projects and public service Internet platforms are concrete digital utopias that point beyond digital capital(ism). Engels’s analysis is updated for critically analysing the digital conditions of the working class today, including the digital labour of hardware assemblers at Foxconn and Pegatron, the digital labour aristocracy of software engineers at Google, online freelance workers, platform workers at capitalist platform corporations such as Uber, Deliveroo, Fiverr, Upwork, or Freelancer, and the digital labour of Facebook users. Engels’s 200th birthday reminds us of the class character of digital capitalism and that we need critical digital social science as a new form of scientific socialism.
Keywords: Friedrich Engels, 200th birthday, anniversary, digital capitalism, digital capital, digital labour, digital commons, The Condition of the Working Class in England, critical digital research, critical digital social science, scientific socialism, international division of digital labour, digital commodity, computational social science, digital positivism, social murder, COVID-19 crisis, coronavirus, pandemic, Foxconn, Pegatron, Google, software engineering, digital labour aristocracy, online freelancers, Uber, Deliveroo, Fiverr, Upwork, Freelancer, Facebook, class struggles, working class, public service Internet platforms, platform co-operatives, Outlines of a Critique of Political Economy; The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State; Anti-Dühring, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy, Dialectics of Nature, Karl Marx
28 November 2020: Friedrich Engels was born 200 years ago on 28 November 1820. Together with Karl Marx, Engels was the founder of the critique of the political economy. He was a theorist, historian, journalist, philosopher, politician and entrepreneur who used the money capital he accumulated for support Marx and the international socialist movement. In 2020, capitalism has changed, but is still around. Engels’s 200th anniversary is a good occasion in order to ask: How relevant are Friedrich Engels’s works in the age of digital capitalism? This essay deals with this question.
Engels together with Marx wrote the Manifesto of the Communist Party, The German Ideology, and The Holy Family. Engels also helped out Marx with writing newspaper articles that appeared under Marx’s name. And he made a genuine contribution to critical theory with works such as Anti-Schelling (Schelling and Revelation), Outlines of a Critique of Political Economy, The Condition of the Working Class in England, The Housing Question, Anti-Dühring, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, Dialectics of Nature; The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State; Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy. This article discusses the relevance of a variety of Engels’s works for the critical analysis of digital capitalism with a special focus on The Condition of the Working Class in England because we are interested in the condition of the working class in digital capitalism today.
Section 2
discusses the
role of history and class struggles in Engels’s works. It deals with the
question whether or not Engels was a vulgariser of Marx’s theory, who
advanced
a deterministic concept of history. Section 3 outlines a critique of
computational social science based on Engels’s understanding of
scientific
socialism. Section 4 analyses the digital condition of the working class
today.
It uses Engels’s works, especially his book The
Condition
of the Working Class in England, for analysing the digital labour
of hardware assemblers, Google software engineers, platform workers, and
Facebook users. The section also analyses the role of productivity gains
achieved by digital automation and robotisation and labour inequalities
in the
COVID-19 crisis. Section 6 discusses working class struggles in digital
capitalism. Section 6 draws conclusions.
Positions on the intellectual relationship of Marx and
Engels are split. There are on the one hand those who argue that
Engels
misunderstood, manipulated and vulgarised Marx’s theory and thereby
not just
turned Marx into Marxism but also laid the grounds for Stalinism (see
e.g. Carver 1981; 1983;
1990; Levine 1975;
2006; Schmidt 1971).
And
there are those who say that Engels made his own contributions to
socialist
theory, but that there is no major theoretical difference between Marx
and
Engels (see e.g. Blackledge 2019, Fülberth
2018; Kopf 2017; Krätke
2020; Mayer 1935). The representatives
of this position hold that Engels was a not just Marx’s best friend,
but also
his closest intellectual companion so that there would be not Marx
without
Engels.
Terrell Carver and Norman Levine are two of the theorists who hold the first position Carver (1981, 93) writes that Marx and Engels had “different approaches to social science and perhaps politics itself”. “Engels’s influence has chiefly been on the theoretical side of Marxism, and his ‘dialectics’ and ‘materialism’ are notably memorialized in official Soviet philosophy” (Carver 1990, 257). Levine (2018, 195-196) argues that Engels neglected: “Engelsian Leninism was founded upon the belief that the meteoric advancement of science made socialism attainable and therefore led to the prioritization of the forces of production. […] Engelsian Leninism rested upon de-politicization” (Levine 2018, 195-196). Levine’s arguments imply that there is a lack of focus on class struggle in Engels’s works.
Stalinism eulogised elements from some of Engels’s works. In his essay
“Dialectical and Historical Materialism”
published
in the History of the Communist
Party of
the Soviet Union Bolsheviks: Short Course – the ideological
bible of
Stalinism –, Stalin (1945) references and
quotes from
Engels’s Anti-Dühring, Dialectics of Nature, and Feuerbach and the End of
Classical German
Philosophy.
Stalin (1945) directly applies some aspects of
the dialectics of nature to society and claims that this means that
revolutions
and the transition to socialism are inevitable:
If the connection between the phenomena of nature and their interdependence are laws of the development of nature, it follows, too, that the connection and interdependence of the phenomena of social life are laws of the development of society, and not something accidental. Hence, social life, the history of society, ceases to be an agglomeration of ‘accidents’, for the history of society becomes a development of society according to regular laws, and the study of the history of society becomes a science (114).
Further, if the passing of slow quantitative changes into rapid and abrupt qualitative changes is a law of development, then it is clear that revolutions made by oppressed classes are a quite natural and inevitable phenomenon (111).
For Stalin, socialism as science
does not
mean a science of society that is different from the natural sciences,
but
deterministic and mechanical social laws of nature operating in
society. The
implication is for Stalin that history develops in a linear manner, it
is for
him a “process of
development from the lower to the higher” (Stalin
1939,
109). Stalin argues that the Soviet Union followed capitalism
and therefore
was a socialist system: “[T]he
U.S.S.R.
has already done away with capitalism and has set up a Socialist
system” (Stalin 1945, 119). His implication
was that
anyone critical of him was bourgeois and anti-socialist. The
mechanical
interpretation of the dialectic legitimated Stalin’s terror against
his
opponents.
The concepts of Aufhebung
(sublation) and the negation of the negation are missing in Stalinist
dialectics. They are however key features of Engels’s dialectics.
Stalin
referred to Engels, but Engels’s interpretation of dialectics was
other than
Stalin’s not based on mechanical and deterministic concepts. Engels is
not be
blamed for Stalinism.
In Engels’s canonical works, there are some problematic formulations.
For example, he writes that “the
capitalist
mode of production has likewise itself created the material
conditions from which it must perish” (Engels
1878, 122)
or that there is the “inevitable downfall” of the
capitalistic mode of
production (Engels 1880, 305). Such
formulations
create the impression that society is governed by mechanistic and
deterministic
laws.
But Engels (1878)
stresses in the same works where the mentioned problematic
formulations can be found
that there is a difference between the negation of the negation in
nature and
in society. The dialectic has in each realm of the world “specific
peculiarities” (Engels 1878, 131). The
“history of the
development of society turns out to be essentially different from that
of
nature” because humans “are all endowed with consciousness, are men
acting with
deliberation or passion, working towards definite goals” (Engels
1888,
387). Humans would act with intentions towards specific goals,
but
the outcomes would often be quite different from the intentions, which
is an
element of chance in society that is, however, “governed by inner,
hidden laws”
(Engels 1888, 387). He describes the
proletarian
revolution as the solution of capitalism’s contradictions (Engels
1880, 325).
“To accomplish this act of universal emancipation is the historical
mission of
the modern proletariat”. A mission does not necessarily succeed. In
these
passages, Engels stresses that society operates on dialectical laws
that are
different from the laws of nature. The question is, however, what a
law is in
society. The more problematic formulations that can be found in these
works can
imply that capitalism automatically breaks down. But more frequently
Engels
stresses in the same works that history is the history of class
struggles, for
example: “In modern history at least it
is,
therefore, proved that all political struggles are class struggles,
and all
class struggles for emancipation, despite their necessarily
political form –
for every class struggle is a political struggle – turn ultimately
on the
question of economic emancipation“ (Engels
1888,
387-388, 391). It is one of the laws of society that change
happens
through human practices and that in class society, class struggle is
the
decisive practice of transformation.
This assumption is also in line with Marx’s and Engels’s view of history
in their early works. In The
Holy Family,
the first work that Marx and Engels co-authored, Engels writes: “History
does
nothing, it ‘possesses no immense wealth’, it ‘wages
no battles’.
It is man, real, living man who does all that, who possesses
and fights;
‘history’ is not, as it were, a person apart, using man as a means to
achieve its
own aims; history is nothing but the activity of man
pursuing his
aims” (Marx and Engels 1845, 93). In The Manifesto of the Communist
Party,
Marx and Engels (1848b, 482) say: “The
history
of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles”.
Marx added
to the law of class struggle the law of the dialectic of structures
and agency,
of societal conditions and practices. Humans “make their own history,
but they
do not make it just as they please; they do not make it under
circumstances
chosen by themselves, but under circumstances directly encountered,
given and
transmitted from the past” (Marx 1852, 103).
Society’s
transformation is based on dialectics of chance/necessity,
freedom/determination, discontinuity/continuity, practices/structural
conditions. In capitalism, the class contradiction and the
contradiction
between productive forces and relations of production with necessity
call forth
crises. The outcome of such crises is not determined and depends on
the results
of class struggles. Society’s dialectic is a dialectic of objective
contradictions and the human subjects’ practices.
If Marx and Engels had assumed that capitalism would automatically break
down and socialism would emerge inevitably, why would they have
engaged in
practical revolutionary activity? Engels participated, for example,
active in
the 1849 revolutionary uprising for democracy in Elberfeld and Baden.
Marx and
Engels were leaders of the League of the Just, the Communist League,
and the
First International. Engels’s single deterministic historical
formulations seem
to have served the rhetorical-political purpose of motivating
revolutionary
optimism among activists.
In a letter to Borgius, Engels (1894) stresses
that humans “make their history themselves, only in given
surroundings
which condition it and on the basis of actual relations already
existing, among
which the economic relations” form “the red thread which runs through
them”.
The notion of the economic as read thread allows us to see the economic,
i.e.
social production, as the universal and common element of all social
realms.
Social production takes on different forms with emergent meanings but
also is
the red thread of society and its various spheres (see Fuchs
2020a).
Blackledge (2019, 240) stresses that by
scientific socialism Engels did not understand “empiricism or
positivism” and
“a mechanical and fatalistic model of agency. “Engels was neither an
empiricist
nor a positivist. And as regards the charge of reductionism, he held
to a
stratified view of natural and social reality according to which
emergent
properties at each level could neither be reduced to laws governing
the levels
below them, nor could the laws through which they operated be
understood in an
empiricist or positivist fashion”.
Engels stresses in Socialism:
Utopian and Scientific in line with Marx’s Grundrisse and Capital that
science
and technology are on the one hand “the most powerful weapon in the
war
of capital against the working-class” (Engels
1880, 314)
and on the other hand important means of emancipation from capitalism
and class
society that support the establishment and reproduction of “the
kingdom of
freedom” beyond necessity (Engels 1880, 324).
Taken together, there is no doubt that there are some problematic
formulations in Engels’s canonical works. But a more pertinent reading
is that
he and Marx interpreted history as a dialectic of class struggles and
structural conditions, which implies that there is no automatic
breakdown of
capitalism. The implication is also, as Tristam Hunt (2009,
361) stresses in his Engels-biography that Engels and Marx are
not to blame
for Stalin’s terror:
In no intelligible sense can Engels or Marx bear culpability for the crimes of historical actors carried out generations later, even if the policies were offered up in their honor. Just as Adam Smith is not to blame for the inequalities of the free market West, nor Martin Luther for the nature of modern Protestant evangelicalism, nor the Prophet Muhammad for the atrocities of Osama bin Laden, so the millions of souls dispatched by Stalinism (or by Mao’s China, Pol Pot’s Cambodia, and Mengistu’s Ethiopia) did not go to their graves on account of two nineteenth-century London philosophers.
Although there are single
problematic passages in Engels’s works that imply that capitalism must
automatically collapse, there are other passages that stress the
difference of
dialectical laws in nature and society and that a key social law found
in class
societies is that humans make their own history under given conditions
and in
class societies do so in the form of class and social struggles.
Scientific socialism
doesn’t mean that society is governed by mechanical laws, but that
socialist
research studies society based on the combination of critical social
theory and
critical empirical social research.
To
speak
of “scientific socialism” doesn’t automatically and not necessarily
apply
a mechanistic and deterministic theory of society that assumes that
capitalism
automatically breaks down and society is determined by natural
economic laws.
The scientific understanding of socialism is not a natural science
applied
society but rather a social science of society (Gesellschaftswissenschaft) that stresses the key role of the
conscious human being, social practices, social production, and social
relations in society. Natural science theories are not necessarily
deterministic and mechanistic. The point is that in the social
sciences, the
positivist tradition treated society based on natural science methods
and
mathematics, which focuses on pure quantification and assumes that
everything
can be calculated. The logic of positivism neglects society’s
qualities and the
fact that not everything social and societal is calculable. We cannot
properly
calculate love, morals, sadness, happiness, (dis)respect, (in)justice,
solidarity,
etc. Society’s social qualities can only be properly analysed by
qualitative
social research methods. Marx and Engels are not as such opposed to
calculation
and quantification, but they are critical of computing as means of
domination
and exploitation that drives capital accumulation and makes the
qualities of
society disappear behind things and numbers. This critique of
quantification as
aspect of capitalist accumulation has been reflected in Georg Lukács’
(1971) notion of reification and Max
Horkheimer’s (1947) notion of
instrumental reason.
In
the contemporary social sciences,
computational social sciences have emerged as a dominant paradigm that
attracts
lots of attention, support, funding and has increasingly been
institutionalised.
David Lazer et al. (2009, 722) define
computational social science as social science that “leverages the
capacity to collect
and analyze data with an unprecedented breadth and depth and scale”
and
operates with “terabytes of data”. In the textbook Introduction to Computational Social Science, Cioffi-Revilla (2014,
2) defines computational social science:
“The new field of Computational Social Science can be defined as the
interdisciplinary investigation of the social universe on many scales,
ranging
from individual actors to the largest groupings, through the medium of
computation. […] Computational social science is based on an information-processing
paradigm of
society” (Cioffi-Revilla 2014, 2).
The Manifesto of Computational
Social Science (Conte et al. 2012)
argues that
computational social science operates with “massive ICT data” (327),
conducts “massive data analysis” (330)
that operates “up to the whole world population”
(331). It is “a
new
field of science in which new type of data, largely made available
by new ICT
applications, can be used to produce large-scale computational
models of social
phenomena” (333). The Manifesto claims that computational social science constitutes
“a
new era” (327).
Computational social scientists set out to radically transform the
social sciences. Computational social science is a new positivism. Its
methods
cannot understand the qualitative features of society such as
motivations,
norms, moral values, feelings, ideologies, experiences.
Cioffi-Revilla (2014, 1) explicitly
situations computational social science in the context of Auguste
Comte’s
“natural science of social systems, complete with statistical and
mathematical
foundations”. Comte was the founder of positivism. Computational
social science
explicitly stands in the context of positivism. The Manifesto of Computational Social Science argues for turning
sociology and the social sciences into a natural science: “sociology
in particular and the social sciences in
general would undergo a dramatic paradigm shift, arising from the
incorporation
of the scientific method of physical sciences” (Conte
et
al. 2012, 341).
The danger is that computer science colonises the social sciences and
leaves no space and time for critical theory, social theory,
philosophy. The
main danger of the computational social sciences is that it makes the
social
sciences uncritical and turns them into administrative sciences (see Fuchs 2017a). Engels warned in a different
context of
the dangers of positivism. He argues against a mathematical method
that is
“reducing qualitative differences to merely quantitative differences
[…] As
Hegel has already shown (Encyclopädie, I, S. 199), this
view, this
‘one-sided mathematical view’, according to which matter must be
looked upon as
having only quantitative determination, but, qualitatively, as
identical
originally, is ‘no other standpoint than that’ of the French
materialism of the
eighteenth century. It is even a retreat to Pythagoras who regarded
quantitative determination as the essence of things” (Engels
1925,
534). For Engels (1925, 469), such
reductive approaches are a form of “naïve materialism”.
Engels criticises mechanical materialism that does not see and analyse
the qualitative and dialectical aspects of the world. Engels in this
passage
refers to the first part of Hegel’s Encyclopaedia,
where Hegel discusses the dialectical logic. The reference is to the
discussion
of pure quantity as aspect of quantity. Hegel writes in this passage
that “when
we look closely at the exclusively mathematical standpoint that is
here
referred to (according to which quantity, which is a definite stage of
the
logical Idea, is identified with the Idea itself) we see that it is
none other
than the standpoint of Materialism”
(Hegel 1830/1991, 159, addition to §99). He
stresses that
“freedom, law, ethical life […] cannot be measured and computed or
expressed in
a mathematical formula” (Hegel 1830/1991, 159,
addition to §99) and that “we know very little about these things and
the
distinction between them, if we simply stick to a ‘more or less’ of
this kind,
and do not advance to some grasp of specific determinacy, which is
here in the
first place qualitative” (Hegel 1830/1991, 160,
addition to §99).
Hegel and Engels remind us that computational social science cannot
grasp society’s dialectical relations that are not easily
quantifiable. It
cannot understand, model, calculate freedom, law, moral judgement,
love, etc.
Its analyses are one-dimensional. Critical social science should
certainly
adopt and experiment with data-driven methods, but not at the expense
of the
engagement with and application of critical theory (Fuchs
2017a). Digital data gathered on social media and other
data-intensive
environments can reveal important aspects of life in contemporary
societies.
What is needed are not simply new forms of prediction and
quantification, but
critical, creative and experimental methods that combine aspects of
quantitative data with a qualitative understanding of humans’
motivations, experiences,
interpretations, norms and values (Fuchs 2017a).
Whereas
Marx and Engels were social scientists who wrote the Communist
Manifesto, some contemporary
social scientists write manifestos for a new positivism and many more
believe
in what such manifestos postulate, which results in the
institutionalisation of
computational social science and big funding for big data-based
methods and
project. Big data analytics and computational social science miss the
difference between society and nature that Engels points out. The
danger is
that they reduce society to quantitative data and neglect its
indeterminate,
open, dialectical qualities.
To speak of “scientific socialism” doesn’t automatically and not
necessarily apply a mechanistic and deterministic theory of society
that
assumes that capitalism automatically breaks down and society is
determined by
natural economic laws. The scientific understanding of socialism is
not a
natural science applied society but rather a social science of society
(Gesellschaftswissenschaft)
that stresses
the key role of the conscious human being, social practices, social
production,
and social relations in society. Natural science theories are not
necessarily
deterministic and mechanistic. The point is that in the social
sciences, the
positivist tradition treated society based on natural science methods
and
mathematics, which focuses on pure quantification and assumes that
everything
can be calculated.
The logic of positivism neglects society’s qualities and the fact that
not everything social and societal is calculable. We cannot properly
calculate
love, morals, sadness, happiness, (dis)respect, (in)justice,
solidarity, etc.
Society’s social qualities can only be properly analysed by
qualitative social
research methods. Marx and Engels are not as such opposed to
calculation and
quantification, but they are critical of computing as means of
domination and
exploitation that drives capital accumulation and makes the qualities
of
society disappear behind things and numbers. This critique of
quantification as
aspect of capitalist accumulation has been reflected in Georg Lukács’
(1971) notion of reification and Max
Horkheimer’s (1947) notion of
instrumental reason.
Computational
social
science is a paradigm in the social sciences that propagates
mathematical
models of society that use big data and predictive algorithms. Engels’s
scientific socialism is critical of positivism. Computational social
science is
a neo-positivism that neglects that qualitative features of society such
as
motivations, norms, moral values, feelings, ideologies, experiences,
love,
death, freedom, or (in)justice that cannot be reduced to mere
quantities.
Computational social science poses the danger of turning the social
sciences
into administrative, instrumental, positivist research that supports
domination
and exploitation and is a branch of computer science that has colonised
the
social sciences.
In this section, we will discuss the situation of the working class in digital capitalism. Engels’s book The Condition of the Working Class in England plays an important role as starting point for such an analysis. The section introduces Engels’s book (subsection 4.1), the relationship of technology and society (subsection 4.2), digital technology and relative surplus-value production (subsection 4.3), absolute surplus-value production at Foxconn (subsection 4.4), play labour at Google (subsection 4.5), precarious platform workers (subsection 4.6), labour in the COVID-19 crisis (subsection 4.7), and Facebook labour (subsection 4.8).
The Condition of
the Working Class in
England
(CWCE) is for many Engels’
most
influential book. Eric J. Hobsbawm writes that “the Condition is
probably
the earliest large work whose analysis is systematically based on the
concept of the Industrial Revolution” (Hobsbawm
1969,
17). It “remains an indispensable work and a landmark in the
fight for the
emancipation of humanity” (Hobsbawm 1969, 17).
David
McLellan (1993, xix) writes that the Condition
is “the first book to have
dealt comprehensively with the industrial working class as a whole
rather than
just with particular groups or industries”. Engels’s method was a
“[r]ich and
complex” form of interdisciplinarity that combined “economics,
philosophy, and
labour history” (McLellan 1993, xix).
Engels
integrated a “rich mass of material” into “an extraordinary unity […]
articulated […] under […] general principles” (Mayer
1935,
62)
Engels
came from a bourgeois family. His
father Friedrich Engels senior (1796-1860) owned the cotton factory
Ermen &
Engels that operated two cotton mills, one in Engelskirchen
(Rhineland) and one
in Manchester (United Kingdom).
Engels
junior conducted the research for
his book The Condition of the
Working
Class in England (CWCE =
Engels 1845) during his stay in
Manchester from 1842
until 1844, where he was supposed to learn his father’s trade. Engels
directly
experienced the working class’ conditions in England and got in touch
with
workers, from whom he learned about their everyday life and the
problems they
faced. Family status does not determine one’s political worldview.
Born into a
capitalist family, Engels became one of the international leaders of
the
communist movement. There is no 1:1 relationship and no mechanic
determination
of culture by the economy. Engels junior became his father’s
representative in
the Manchester business. After the death of his father in 1860, Engels
became
the co-owner of the Manchester establishment. He managed the company,
funded
Marx’s life in London, financially and intellectually supported the
socialist
movement, and was active as a writer. In 1869, Engels had accumulated
enough
wealth in order to be able to sustain himself and Marx and family, and
support
the socialist movement. He sold his share in Ermen & Engels,
retired from
the company, and entirely devoted himself to the socialist movement
and theory.
In
CWCE, Engels analyses the
rise, early
development and consequences of capitalism in England. The decisive
features he
mentions are a) the working class, b) industrial technologies such as
the
steam-engine as moving technology and manufacturing machinery as
working
technology that replaced handicraft, c) the capitalist class, and d)
the
division of labour.
In
CWCE,
Engels analyses the terrible conditions that the working class had
to
endure in industrial England, including long working hours, low wages,
poverty,
overcrowded and dirty slums and dwellings, poisonous and uneatable
food,
overwork, starvation, death by hunger, lack of sleep, air pollution,
untreated
illnesses, egotism and moral indifference, crime, alcoholism, bad
clothes,
unemployment, rape, homelessness, lack of clean water, drainage and
sanitation,
illiteracy, child labour, military drill in factories, overseers’
flogging and
maltreatment of workers, deadly work accidents, fines, etc.
Engels
characterises the misery the
working class faces as “a condition unworthy of human beings” (CWCE, 43),
conditions where humans cannot
“think, feel, and live as human beings” (CWCE, 220),
degradation
to “the lowest stage of humanity” (CWCE, 73),
treatment
of workers “as mere material, a mere chattel” (CWCE, 66).
Engels
characterisation of capitalism as dehumanising resembles Marx’s
introduction of the notion of alienation in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, where Marx (1844,
517) speaks of one aspect of alienation as “alienation
of the human being from being
human”[1].
Out of such words speaks the deep humanism of Engels and Marx. They
both
understand socialism is a humanist society that enables a good life
for all
humans.
Using
factory inspectors’ reports,
parliamentary reports, observation, and the analysis of news reports,
The Condition of the Working
Class in
England shows that Engels already in the 1840s practiced and
pioneered
empirical social research (Kurz 2020, 67; Krätke 2020, 29-34; Zimmermann
2020). In Capital Volume
1, Marx
(1867) uses the same empirical method as
Engels in
CWCE, which shows that Engels’s work had large influence on Marx. Marx
(1867, 349 (footnote 15), 573, 755),
explicitly refers
positively to Engels’s book several times. For example, Marx (1867,
349 [footnote 15]) writes:
How well Engels understood the spirit of the capitalist mode of production is shown by the Factory Reports, Reports on Mines, etc. which have appeared since 1845, and how wonderfully he painted the circumstances in detail is seen on the most superficial comparison of his work with the official reports of the Children's Employment Commission, published eighteen to twenty years later (1863-7).
Working on Capital, Marx re-read Engels’s Condition and wrote to him about the book: “With what zest and passion, what boldness of vision and absence of all learned or scientific reservations, the subject is still attacked in these pages!” (Marx 1863, 469).
Some observers, such as McLellan (1993, xviii) argue that underlying Engels approach in CWCE is “a technological determinism that was to remain with Engels all his life”. There are indeed some formulations in CWCE that can create such an impression: The “industrial revolution […] altered the whole civil society” (CWCE, 15); the “proletariat was called into existence by the introduction of machinery” (CWCE, 29)
But Engels leaves no doubt that capitalist relations of production, i.e.
private property relations, the class relation between capital and
labour and
the profit imperative, shape the development and application of
machinery. He
says that capitalism is the cause of misery: The “great central fact”
is “that
the cause of the miserable condition of the working class is to be
sought […]
in the capitalistic system
itself” (CWCE, 314). When discussing
machinery,
Engels points out that the social conditions under which technology
exist are
the factors that have decisive influence on technology’s impacts on
society:
“The consequences of improvement in machinery under our present social
conditions are, for the working man, solely injurious, and often in
the highest
degree oppressive” (CWCE, 149).
In CWCE, Engels often describes class relations as competition and makes
clear that not machines, but transformation of class relations created
the
proletariat. Competition – “the battle of all against all” – “created
and
extended the proletariat” (CWCE, 87).
Capitalist competition means a class conflict between capital and
labour but
also competition between capitalists that results in the
centralisation of
capital and competition between workers, such as between the
“power-loom
weaver” and “the hand-loom weaver” (CWCE, 87).
Engels (Marx and Engels 1848b, 482)
inserted a note to the 1888 edition of the Manifesto,
saying that by “bourgeoisie is meant the class of modern Capitalists,
owners of
the means of social production and employers of wage-labour. By
proletariat,
the class of modern wage-labourers who, having no means of production
of their
own, are reduced to selling their labour-power in order to live”.
Capital means
“the direct or indirect control of the means of subsistence and
production” as
“the weapon with which this social warfare is carried on” (CWCE, 37-38).
The
bourgeoisie is the class of property-holders (CWCE, 281).
The
bourgeoise measures “[a]ll the conditions of life […] by money” (CWCE, 282).
The decisive aspect of
technology in capitalism is that capitalists own technologies as
private
property that is a means of production used for accumulating capital
and the
production of surplus-value and commodities.
Also in Outlines of a Critique of
Political Economy, a foundational text of Marx’s and Engels’s
approach,
young Engels (1843, 442-443)
stresses that science and technology are instruments in the hands of
the
bourgeoisie:
In
the struggle of capital and land against labour,
the first two elements enjoy yet another special advantage over labour
– the assistance
of science; for in present conditions science, too, is directed
against labour.
Almost all mechanical inventions, for instance, have been occasioned
by the
lack of labour-power; in particular Hargreaves’, Crompton’s and
Arkwright’s
cotton-spinning machines. There has never been an intense demand for
labour
which did not result in an invention that increased labour
productivity
considerably, thus diverting demand away from human labour. The
history of
England from 1770 until now is a continuous demonstration of this. The
last
great invention in cotton-spinning, the self-acting mule, was
occasioned solely
by the demand for labour, and rising wages. It doubled machine-labour,
and
thereby cut down hand-labour by half; it threw half the workers out of
employment,
and thereby reduced the wages of the others by half; it crushed a plot
of the
workers against the factory owners, and destroyed the last vestige of
strength
with which labour had still held out in the unequal struggle against
capital.
Marx
(1859, 264) characterised the Outlines as “brilliant essay on the critique of economic
categories” and directly referred to it several times in Capital
Volume I (Marx 1867, 168 [footnote 30], 253
[footnote
5], 266-267 [footnote 20], 788
[footnote 15]). In the Outlines, Engels points out
that “the mental element of invention, of thought” (Engels
1843,
427), as in the form of science, is part of human labour and the
“human, subjective side, labour” (427) of
production.
In work, the human being is “active physically and mentally” (428).
Engels here on the one hand points out the
dialectic of mental and physical activity in work and on the other
hand
identified mental work, or what today is often called knowledge or
information
work, as important aspect of production.
The assumption that Engels was a
technological determinist cannot be sustained. He analysed technology
in
capitalism as embedded into class relations so that there is
capitalist
ownership of technology as private-property that is utilised as means
for the
production of surplus-value, commodities, and profit.
In the Grundrisse, Marx (1857/58) introduced the notion of surplus-value, by which he means that workers produce unpaid labour during a portion of the working by that capitalists appropriate and turn into monetary profit. Marx (1867, 645) distinguishes two methods of surplus-value production: “The production of absolute surplus-value turns exclusively on the length of the working day, whereas the production of relative surplus-value completely revolutionizes the technical processes of labour and the groupings into which society is divided”. Absolute surplus-value production means the lengthening of the unpaid part of the working day. Relative surplus-value production is the increase of productivity so that more value is produced during a certain time period than before. Engels anticipated both concepts in CWCE.
Engels gives many concrete examples of the increase of productivity through the introduction of new technologies. In the cotton industry, the invention of the jenny “made it possible to deliver more yarn than heretofore” (CWCE, 18). The introduction of the power-loom further increased the productivity of the English cotton industry: “In the years 1771-1775, there were annually imported into England rather less than 5,000,000 pounds of raw cotton; in the year 1841 there were imported 528,000,000 pounds, and the import for 1844 will reach at least 600,000,000 pounds” (CWCE, 21). Similar productivity increases could be observed in other industries, for example the manufacturing of wool: “In 1738 there were 75,000 pieces of woollen cloth produced in the West Riding of Yorkshire; in 1817 there were 490,000 pieces, and so rapid was the extension of the industry that in 1854, 450,000 more pieces were produced than in 1825. In 1801, 101,000,000 pounds of wool (7,000,000 pounds of it imported) were worked up; in 1855, 180,000,000 pounds were worked up, of which 42,000,000 pounds were imported” (CWCE, 22-23).
Engels describes the phenomenon of relative surplus-value production, but did not have a theoretical concept naming this process. Marx later introduced based on Engels the concepts of surplus-value and the methods of surplus-value production.
Since the middle of the 20th century, The capitalist invention and the capitalist application of digital production technologies has led to significant increases of productivity. Just like Engels observed the impacts of technologies such as the steam-engine and the power-loom, we today can observe the effects of the digitalisation of production that has increased productivity.
Table 1: Total annual labour productivity growth in manufacturing in percentage, productivity is measured as labour productivity per unit labour input (in most cases gross value added in constant prices per hour worked), data source: OECD STAN
Table 1 shows productivity growth
data for
the G7-economies. It uses labour productivity growth as a measure of
productivity. Labour productivity is a statistical measure of the
gross value
added (measured in constant US$) produced per hour worked in a
particular
industry. It calculates labour productivity by diving the total value
added in
an industry during one year by the total amount of working hours in
that
industry. The data in table 1 shows the ten-year growth rate of labour
productivity. Not all data was available, so some fields have been
left
undefined. In advanced capitalist countries, labour productivity has
more than
doubled over a time period of forty years (1970-2010). In the analysed
national
economies, it takes on average between 26 and 44 years to double the
productivity of manufacturing. This was also the time when computing
was
introduced in manufacturing as a production technology. Capitalist
digitalisation has resulted in large productivity growth in
manufacturing and
other industries.
Industry 4.0 is about technologies that combine the Internet of Things,
Big Data, social media, cloud computing, sensors, artificial
intelligence and
robotics in the production, distribution and use of physical goods.
The
bourgeoisie has declared the fourth industrial revolution to try to
automate
the production, distribution, handling, repair and disposal of
industrial goods
such as cars (Fuchs 2018c). It hopes to
increase the
profit rate of the manufacturing industry.
Engels pointed out that the capitalist shaping and use of industrial
technologies turned workers into “machines pure and simple” (CWCE, 17).
The capitalist shaping,
development, design and use of digital technologies has contributed to
forms of
alienation such as the enslavement of mine workers who extract the
physical
resources out of which digital hardware is manufactured, long working
hours in
the assemblage of hardware and in the
software and creative industry, an always-on-work-culture
mediated by
laptops, phones and tablets as means of production, precarious
freelancing in
the digital industries, etc.
Engels gives a picture of the
terrible
conditions that members of the working
faced
in England in the 1840s. One of his examples are the dress-makers in
London:
They employ a mass of young girls – there are said to be 15,000 of them in all – who sleep and eat on the premises, come usually from the country, and are therefore absolutely the slaves of their employers. During the fashionable season, which lasts some four months, working-hours, even in the best establishments, are fifteen, and, in very pressing cases, eighteen a day; but in most shops work goes on at these times without any set regulation, so that the girls never have more than six, often not more than three or four, sometimes, indeed, not more than two hours in the twenty-four, for rest and sleep, working nineteen to twenty-two hours, if not the whole night through, as frequently happens! The only limit set to their work is the absolute physical inability to hold the needle another minute (CWCE, 217).
Here's another example of long
working hours
that Engels describes:
Other manufacturers were yet more barbarous, requiring many heads to work thirty to forty hours at a stretch, several times a week, letting them get a couple of hours of sleep only, because the night-shift was not complete, but calculated to replace a part of the operatives only. […] The consequences of these cruelties became evident quickly enough. The Commissioners mention a crowd of cripples who appeared before them, who clearly owed their distortion to the long working hours. This distortion usually consists of a curving of the spinal column and legs (CWCE, 161-162).
What Engels analyses here is the
method of
absolute surplus-value production. Capitalist have the interest to
make workers
produce commodities for as many hours per day and per week as possible
for as
little wage as possible. Long hours and small wages promise high
profits.
Absolute surplus-value production is also an important method of
surplus-value production in 21st-century digital capitalism. In the
period from
1992 until 2019, the number of agricultural workers in China decreased
from 350
million to 120 million, the number of manufacturing workers increased
from 180
million to 200 million, and the number of service workers went from
120 million
to 440 million[2].
Unlike economic development in Western capitalism, where the rise of
the
service and information industries was accompanied by the shrinking of
agriculture and manufacturing, China’s capitalism with Chinese
characteristics
(Harvey 2005, chapter 5) combines
industrialisation
and informatisation as simultaneous processes.
Western transnational digital corporations such as Apple, Dell, HP, and
AsusTek make use of Chinese large and comparatively cheap labour force
in order
to export capital so that digital hardware is assembled in China by
workers
contracted by suppliers such as Foxconn, Pegatron, Compal Electronics,
or
Wistron. The goal is to increase profits by minimising labour costs.
Students & Scholars Against Corporate Misbehaviour (SACOM) (2011) reported that workers at the Chinese factories at Foxconn, where iPhones and other hardware is assembled, faced conditions such as military drill, forced and unpaid overtime, fines such as the non-payment of wages, crowded accommodations, low wages, compulsory internships, toxic workplaces, etc. In 2010/2011, nineteen young Foxconn workers aged between 17 and 28 attempted to commit suicide by jumping from Foxconn buildings. Most of them died. They could no longer stand the terrible working conditions.
China Labor Watch (2017,
1, 3) conducted research in order to find
out how the working conditions look like in the factories of the Apple
suppliers Compal, Foxconn, Green Point, and Pegatron:
In all of the four factories, weekly working hours surpassed 60 hours and monthly overtime hours surpassed 90 hours, with most overtime amounting to of 136 hours over a month. […] Workers were required to sign an agreement to voluntarily do overtime, opt out of paying for social insurance and opt out of housing funds. These acts are blatant attempts to evade responsibilities and are clear violations against China’s Labor Law. […] Workers at Pegatron and Green Point were continuously working overtime without compensation. […] Both excessive working hours and tremendous pressure are severe problems at Foxconn. Since 2010, there have been more than 10 suicides, indicative of the terrible working conditions and rigid management. In September 2016, [a] CLW [China Labour Watch] investigator launched another undercover investigation at Foxconn. […] Most workers there had accumulated 122 hours of overtime each month […], far exceeding the legal limit of 36 hours per month as per China’s labor laws.
Just like the dress-makers whose
labour
Engels analysed in the 1840s, 21st-century digital hardware assemblage
workers
at Foxconn, Pegatron and other suppliers are a largely young and
female
workforce that is highly exploited. Capitalist hardware corporations
try to
make workers conduct a high number of weekly working hours for low pay
and with
unpaid overtime in order to minimise production costs so that these
transnational corporations profits can be maximised. The Chinese
manufacturing
industry is part of a global capitalist system, in which transnational
corporations outsource labour to Asia in order to accumulate capital
by making
use of the method of absolute surplus-value production. China’s large
working
class, whose members often leave rural areas in order to find work in
urban manufacturing
centres, is transnational corporations’ source of cheap and highly
exploited
labour.
Engels describes a faction of the
working
class that was relatively privileged. These were workers whose “state
of misery
and insecurity in which they live now is as low as ever” (CWCE, 321).
He
terms these workers the labour aristocracy, “an aristocracy among the
working-class” (engineers, carpenters, joiners, bricklayers) that has
“succeeded in enforcing for themselves a relatively comfortable
position” (CWCE,
321). Lenin (1920,
194) uses the notion of the labour aristocracy for
“workers-turned-bourgeois”, “who are quite philistine in their mode of
life, in
the size of their earnings and in their entire outlook”. “They are the
real agents
of the bourgeoisie in the working-class movement, the labour
lieutenants of
the capitalist class”.
Software engineers are a digital labour aristocracy. They tend to earn
very high wages, which gives them a privileged position. The demand
for their
labour-power is very high. Although many software engineers are
relatively rich
money-wise, they are socially poor. They often lack social relations
friendships, outside of the office. They spend most of their time in
offices
such as the Googleplex, where they work long hours. Many software
companies
want to keep them in the office by providing facilities for sports,
entertainment, relaxation, etc. The Googleplex more looks like a
playground
than an office. In the life of software engineers, labour and play
converge.
Google workers are playworkers, workers for whom labour feels like
play.
Google workers in comparison to ICT manufacturers have much higher wages
and privileges, which also means that they are more unlikely to
resist, which
is, as Engels describes, typical for the labour aristocracy: “they are
very
nice people indeed nowadays to deal with, for any sensible capitalist
in
particular and for the whole capitalist class in general” (CWCE, 321).
This passage from Friedrich Engels’s book The Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844 describes
typical working conditions in the phase of the industrialization of
capitalism:
work in factories was mentally and physically highly exhausting, had
negative
health impacts, and was highly controlled by factory owners and
security
forces.
The manufacturing labour that Engels analysed in the 1840s was
physically highly exhausting. Programming does not require engineers
to burn
lots of energy. Whereas manufacturing labour feels like toil, Google
labour
tends to feel like play.
Like at the time of Engels engineers, carpenters, joiners, bricklayers,
in digital capitalism software engineers hold qualifications and
produce goods
that are in high demand and allow achieving relatively high wages and
income.
The poor workers who Engels portrays in CWCE
as toiling in industries such as cotton and wool manufacturing,
dress-making,
etc. were compelled to work long hours by poverty wages and the
“silent
compulsion of economic relations” (Marx 1867, 899)
of
the labour-market that makes them starve if they don’t sell their
labour-power.
Poverty-wages were used as a means of coercion, as a method of
absolute
surplus-value production. The contemporary digital labour aristocracy
also
faces the silent compulsion of having to sell their wages. But these
wages are
very high because they work in a highly productive industry that
produces a key
commodity – software – that plays an influential role in almost all
parts of
the 21st century society. Digitalisation transforms all
aspects of
society, which is why software is in high demand and allows achieving
high
profits and commodity prices. Those who possess the key skill of
knowing how to
code software can therefore in turn achieve high wages. Absolute
surplus-value
production takes on a new form in this industry: software engineers
often sign
all-inclusive contracts that fixes a certain wage-sum per month
without
extra-pay for overtime. In the USA, the Fair US Labor Standards Act
(Section 13
[a] 17) enables software corporations such as Google not to pay
overtime if
there is an hourly wage of at least US$ 27.63. This law legally enacts
absolute surplus-value
production in
the US software industry.
In addition, new management methods
that try to blur the distinction between labour-time/spare-time and
between
workspace/private spaces are often used in software corporations in
order to
keep the workers in the company for long hours, which makes them work
overtime
and to experience the long hours they spend in their employers’
premises not as
alienation, but as play and fun. The result is that they work longer
hours that
are unpaid. Absolute surplus-value production in key sectors of 21st
century digital capitalism such as the software industry takes on the
form of
play labour.
The first, second, and third edition of my book Social Media: A Critical Introduction contains a chapter about the
critique of the political economy of Google (Fuchs 2014, chapter 6; Fuchs
2017b,
chapter 6; Fuchs 2021, chapter 5).
For this
chapter, I analysed online forums, where Google workers report on
their working
conditions. I updated this analysis for each edition (2014,
2017, 2021). The
working
conditions at Google stayed constant during this time: Google
employees enjoy
the content of their job, the perks such as free food and working for
a
high-reputation brand, but complain about the lack of work-life
balance. When
asked about working conditions at Google, they typical Google
software-engineer
says that “work/life
balance is
nearly non-existent” and one must be prepared to “work all day and
night long”
(Fuchs 2021, chapter 5).
Google employees enjoy the idea of
working
in a high-reputation company, tend to find their work tasks
interesting, like
the perks such as free food, but tend to complain about the long
working hours,
a lot of overtime, and the lack of work‒life balance. Lack of
work-life
balance at companies such as Google mays a playful work environment
that turns
spare-time into unpaid labour-time.
Luc Boltanski
and Ève Chiapello (2005) speak
in this
context of the “new spirit of capitalism”. The new spirit of
capitalism is a
management method and management ideology. It promises labour that is
characterised by
autonomy, spontaneity, rhizomorphous capacity, multitasking (in contrast to the narrow specialization of the old division of labour), conviviality, openness to others and novelty, availability, creativity, visionary intuition, sensitivity to differences, listening to lived experience and receptiveness to a whole range of experiences, being attracted to informality and the search for interpersonal contacts (Boltanski and Chiapello 2005, 97).
Such
promises
“are taken directly from the repertoire of May 1968” (Boltanski
and Chiapello 2005, 97). The new
spirit of capitalism is a work culture of creativity, play, and fun
that
capital uses as new, sophisticated method of absolute surplus-value
production
that blurs establish distinctions and demarcations of space and time
in the
economy. Inspired by Boltanski and Chiapello, Eran Fisher summarises
these
changes in the following way:
It
is therefore best understood in
terms of the eradication of the distinctions between these components:
between companies
and the network, producers and consumers, producers and users, labor and
fun,
forces of production and the production process, and so forth. These
established industrial demarcations (and more specifically, part and
parcel of
the Fordist phase of capitalism) are now overturned with the emergence
of
network production (Fisher 2010, 140).
Figure 1: A google ad for jobs at the Googleplex. Source: https://careers.google.com/locations/mountain-view/?hl=en, accessed 11 July 2020
Figure 1 shows a typical Google
job-ad. It
advertises a variety of jobs such as software engineer, designer,
business
strategist, marketing, sales support, policy and privacy manager, etc.
in
Googleplex, the company headquarter in Mountain View, California.
Google in
this ad lauds itself for proving worker “[o]nsite benefits like
fitness and
wellness centers”, “a group cooking class”, “coffee tasting”, riding
“a gBike
to one of our cafés”. The business philosophy is that “taking care of
Googlers
is good for us all”. The point is that these benefits that promise
fun,
relaxation and entertainment are “onsite”: They keep Googlers at the
Google
premises and turn leisure time into labour time. When workers attend
yoga and
fitness classes, cooking classes, cafés etc. at the workplace, then
the
reproduction of their labour-power takes place at the workplace so
that there is
no clear spatial and temporal demarcation of labour time and
relaxation. The
three images in the job ad symbolise the blurring of space and time at
Google:
coding, chatting with colleagues in a café, a and relaxation in a
garden are
presented as integral parts of work at Google. Googlers do not leave
the
workplace for leisure time, but stay at the Google workplace. They
blurring
boundaries between workspace and playground and between worktime and
leisure-time result in an increase of unpaid labour-time. For Google
workers,
lifetime becomes Google time and value-creating labour-time. What
Google means
by saying that “taking care of Googlers is good for us all” is that
providing a
playful work environment is a method of exploitation by absolute
surplus-value
production that is good for Google’s profits.
Digital capitalism has also given rise to platform workers. These are workers who mostly are freelancers and use apps and Internet platforms for finding work. Examples are the Uber and DiDi taxi driver, the Deliveroo biker who delivers food, and the online freelancer who uses platforms such as Fiverr, Upwork, or Freelancer for finding work. All of these platforms have in common that they are large capitalist corporations that own a proprietary software programme that platform workers use in order to find customers. The platform is a key means of production that is privately owned by digital corporations. Without access to this platform, the freelancers cannot find customers. They depend on this means of production. Formally speaking they are self-employed, but in reality they are workers who are exploited by digital platforms that control the key means of production as private property and capital. For each service organised via the platform, the capitalist platform corporation typically charges a share of the service price. It makes profit by renting out its platform to freelancers who produce a service commodity that is sold to customers that are found via the platform’s algorithms. Platform capitalists typically advertise their platforms as enabling flexible work that allows workers to earn lots of money. Figures 2 and 3 show two examples.
Figure 2: Deliveroo’s self-presentation as platform that enables
workers’
freedom. Source: https://deliveroo.co.uk,
accessed 11 July 2020
Figure 3: Uber’s self-presentation as platform that enables workers’ freedom. Source: https://www.uber.com/at/en/drive/, accessed 11 July 2020
The common narrative of these
self-presentations is that freelancer platforms enable and support
workers’
freedom to be their own boss and determine their work times
themselves, and in
doing so earn lots of money. The reality is that platform workers are
very
often highly exploited, precarious workers who work long hours to
survive (see Fuchs 2021, chapters 11 & 12;
Fuchs
2017b, chapter 10).
Platform workers are often piece-workers. They are not paid by the hour,
but for each completed service, each piece of work. Karl Marx (1867)
dedicates chapter 21 in Capital Volume 1 to piece-wages (see also Fuchs
2016,
chapter 21). He characterises piece-work and piece-wages as the
most
fruitful source of reductions on wages, and of frauds committed by the
capitalists” (Marx 1867, 694). Platform labour
is a
contemporary form of piece-labour and piece-wages in digital
capitalism that
aims at platform capitalists’ reduction of investment costs for
maximising
profits. If platforms such as Uber had to pay its drivers per hour, it
might
make much less profit than it does when charging a percentage share of
the
piece-price. Platform capitalism is a dimension of digital capitalism
that advances
highly precarious labour.
In CWCE, Engels describes the
working conditions of needlewomen, who were paid per piece. They were
low-paid
and conducted highly tiresome labour. “With the same cruelty, though
somewhat
more indirectly, the rest of the needle-women of London are exploited.
The
girls employed in stay-making have a hard, wearing occupation, trying
to the
eyes. And what wages do they get? I do not know; but this I know, that
the
middleman who has to give security for the material delivered, and who
distributes the work among the needle-women, receives 1½d. per piece”
(CWCE, 218). In digital
capitalist society,
transnational digital corporations such as Uber, Deliveroo, Fiverr, or
Upwork are
the contemporary middlemen that exploit digital pieceworkers.
The 2020 COVID-19 crisis has
resulted in
radical changes of society and the economy. In many countries,
societies were “shut down” in order to
lower the infection risk. Many people stayed at home and worked from
home. The
economy and society thereby underwent substantial changes (Fuchs
2020b). Working at a physical distance mediated by
Internet-based
communication and co-operation technologies became widespread. Many
knowledge
and service workers, who normally conduct their work face-to-face in
offices,
started working at a distance from home. Workers such as academics,
teachers,
general practitioners, engineers, lawyers, consultants, artists, etc.
became
digital workers, who conduct services at a distance from their homes.
Their
homes became a supra-locale where working life, private life,
education,
leisure, etc. converged (Fuchs 2020b).
In the coronavirus crisis, being a digital worker who can work from home
is a privilege that reduces the risk of unemployment, illness, and
death. Other
workers, especially those in the tourism industry, personal services,
the
hospitality industry, and the culture and entertainment industry, who
cannot
conduct their services from a distance, lost their jobs. Key sector
workers
such as food workers, supermarket workers, or health care workers, who
work in
industries that are absolutely essential for society, couldn’t work
from a
distance and a shutdown of these realms of work was impossible.
Because of a
lack of personal protective equipment, workers in key sectors faced a
much
higher risk to get infected by and die from COVID-19.
Amazon’s online shopping business boomed during the coronavirus-crisis.
In the first financial quarter of 2020, its revenues increased from
59.7
billion US$ from the same period in 2019 to 75.5 billion, which is an
increase
by 26.5 percent[3].
Amazon’s stock price increased from US$ 1,900 US-dollar at the start
of 2020 to
US$ 3,200 in the middle of July 2020[4].
Amazon is the world’s 22nd largest transnational
corporation with
annual profits of US$ 10.6 billion in 2019[5].
In 2020. Amazon founder and CEO Jeff Bezos was with a total wealth of
US$ 113
the world’s richest person[6].
Amazon workers are precarious service workers who according to reports
faced
the risk of getting infected by COVID-19:
In order to meet the demands of a country in which homes must suddenly be retrofitted to accommodate classrooms, co-working spaces, gyms, hair salons and so on, Amazon announced last month that it would hire 100,000 additional workers in its fulfillment centers and delivery networks, jobs for which many people will be desperate, given the decimated state of the retail and service industries. […] Though the company has increased pay by $2 an hour, employees around the country at Amazon warehouses and its subsidiary, Whole Foods, have been staging walkouts to demand better health protections during the pandemic. For years, Amazon has resisted the efforts of organized labor. […] In a letter to Mr. Bezos, […] labor leaders also addressed concerns that conditions at Amazon warehouses were unsafe: workers there were ‘reporting crowded spaces, a required rate of work that does not allow for proper sanitizing of work spaces, and empty containers meant to hold sanitizing wipes’. […[ various colleagues coming to work […] [were] unwell: fatigued, lightheaded, nauseous […] Later in the month, one of his colleagues, Barbara Chandler, tested positive for the coronavirus. She was advised by those in human resources at the facility to keep the news on the ‘down low’,’ she told me. Frustrated by what he perceived as the company’s lack of transparency, Mr. Smalls made it his mission to disseminate information about cases of Covid-19 at the warehouse (Bellafante 2020).
Amazon workers in countries such as
the USA,
France, and Italy protested against these conditions. Amazon has not
released
data on the number of its workers that got infected and the number of
those
that died. In the Amazon warehouse in Shakopee, Minnesota, 88 out of
1,000
employees got infected within 70 days (García-Hodges,
Kent
and Kaplan 2020).
Tönnies
Holding is
a German meat processing corporation that has more than 16,500
employees and.
Its headquarters are in Rheda-Wiedenbrück,
a
town in the German state of North
Rhine-Westphalia, where the company also operates a large meat
processing
plant. In 2018, the company achieved annual revenues of 6.65 billion
Euros[7]. In 2020, the wealth of
Clemens Tönnies and Robert Tönnies, who are the two major owners the
Tönnies
Holding, was US$ 1.8 billion each, which equally placed them as the
world’s 1196th
richest persons in 2020[8]. In summer 2020, there
were more than 1,500 COVID-19 cases among workers in the Tönnies
factory in Rheda-Wiedenbrück,
among them many low-paid migrant workers
who are bogus self-employed and live in crowded accommodations.
The agglomeration of workers in crowded spaces played a role in the
spread of COVID-19 among Tönnies-workers. A report in Der Spiegel describes the conditions that the predominantly Eastern
European Tönnies-workers faced in Rheda-Wiedenbrück:
They tend to be hired by subcontractors, they are poorly paid, quickly replaced and inadequately protected – even during the current coronavirus pandemic. […] Now, Clemens Tönnies – sometimes referred to as the Pork Chop Prince or the Meat Baron – has a problem. For years, he has ruthlessly pursued efficiency, but now, the entire country wants to know what goes on behind his factory gates. He has perfected the art of extracting all he can out of both his employees and the animals they process, transforming living creatures into an industrial product. His strategy was volume, volume, volume and he cut his costs to the bone, becoming the favorite supplier to Germany's discount grocery chains. The company enjoys a 30 percent share of the pork market in Germany. […] A Polish worker in Rheda-Wiedenbrück has a bit more to say, though he is fearful of speaking openly. He says he earns 1,600 euros for 190 hours of work per month. His shifts begin at 3 a.m. and end at 1 p.m., with a 30-minute break every three hours. ‘We stand at the conveyor belt about 20 to 30 centimeters apart, right next to each other. Often, the speed of the belt is ratcheted up and the supervisor watches us closely’. […] Like the Romanians in the white-plastered house near Münster, many workers aren't actually Tönnies employees, instead working for subcontractors, and without them […] According to Tönnies Holding, 50 percent of its workers are actually employees of such a company (Becker et al. 2014, 10-11; 11; 14)
Romanian
Tönnies
workers described the housing conditions they faced:
Romanian
worker: “It
was always very crowded; there were sometimes 10, 12, occasionally even
14
people in one apartment. The monthly rent was 200 euros each. The
buildings
belonged to the subcontractors. […] But it just isn't fair to cram so
many
people into one apartment!” (Deutsche
Welle 2020a)
Most workers interviewed, many of whom were very upset, have been either employed by the huge meat producer Tönnies or its subsidiaries. They have described extremely exhaustive work and aggressive language. The workers accused managers of not putting enough protective measures in place in the wake of the COVID-19 pandemic. Some have also said that the shared accommodation, in which they were forced to live, was cramped and inhumane” (Deutsche Welle 2020b).
In CWCE, Engels introduces the notion of social murder, by which he means poor working conditions that endanger the lives of workers. Social murder means that workers die “indirectly, far more than directly” (CWCE, 38) through social structures that cause the death of workers and that “society places hundreds of proletarians in such a position that they inevitably meet a too early and an unnatural death, one which is quite as much a death by violence as that by the sword or bullet; when it deprives thousands of the necessaries of life, places them under conditions in which they cannot live ” (CWCE, 106). Capitalism places
the workers
under
conditions in which they can neither retain health nor live long; that
it
undermines the vital force of these workers gradually, little by little,
and so
hurries them to the grave before their time. I have further to prove
that
society knows how injurious such conditions are to the health and the
life of
the workers, and yet does nothing to improve these conditions. That it knows
the consequences of its deeds; that its act is, therefore, not mere
manslaughter, but murder (CWCE, 107).
CWCE’s second chapter “The Great Towns”
focuses
on spatial conditions of working class life. It is an analysis of
everyday
urban life. Engels described how in English working class districts
“many human
beings here lived crowded into a small space” (CWCE, 39)
where there is “little
air – and
such air!” to breathe (CWCE, 65). 175 years after
Engels published
CWCE in 1845, poor working conditions and the racist exploitation of
migrant
workers have in the COVID-19 crisis created new forms of social
murder where
workers cannot keep social distance and working conditions result in
COVID-19
that makes it hard for infected poor workers to breathe and results
in the
death of a specific share of those who caught the virus.
The Tönnies-scandal shows that 170 years after Engels’s report on the conditions of the working class, poor and highly exploited workers still face threats to their health and life due to the agglomeration of many workers in cramped spaces. In the COVID-19 crisis, the poorest cannot afford social distancing and are forced to risk their lives. Capital draws profits from these risks because space is considered as a production factor of capital so that crowding workers into small work and living spaces increases profitability. Tönnies makes profits by low wages for long hours. And subcontractors in addition rob parts of the workers’ wages by charging high rents for overcrowded substandard accommodation. Renting out small places to extremely vulnerable workers allows rentiers to divide space into small compartments and to command a high rental price for these compartments. In addition, by keeping the compartments in a shabby condition, the rentier tries to keep his investment costs low in order to be able to maximise their gains.
Amazon and Tönnies are examples of companies that have been criticised
by observers in the context of COVID-19. These observers have argued
that
workers were put at risk of catching the virus by a lack of protective
measures. Work inequalities have been reinforced on the COVID-19
crisis.
Migrant workers and unskilled workers are more likely to have jobs
that cannot
be conducted over a distance. Slaughtering animals and packing books
into
parcels have not-yet been fully automated and robotised. They cannot
be
conducted at a distance via the Internet. Low-paid, low-skill workers who cannot work from a distance have faced
an increased risk of catching COVID-19 and dying from the virus. In
the
COVID-19 crisis, social murder has taken on new forms.
In
the
book The Origin of the Family,
Private Property and the State, Engels (1892,
131-132)
gives a definition of materialism:
According to the materialist conception, the determining factor in history is, in the last resort, the production and reproduction of immediate life. But this itself is again of a twofold character. On the one hand, the production of the means of subsistence, of food, clothing and shelter and the implements required for this; on the other, the production of human beings themselves, the propagation of the species.
Materialism in society is the
insight that
social production is the key factor of all societies and social
realms. What
Engels’s passage allows us to understand is that social production as
the
foundation of society is not limited to the office and the factory,
but extends
into all realms of society, including the family. Engels’s formulation
has been
influential on and led to discussions in Marxist and socialist
feminism (e.g. Barrett 1980, 48-49, 131-132;
Eisenstein 1979; Federici
2012,
1; Fraser and Jaeggi 2018, 32;
Gimenez 1987; Haug
2015; Leacock 2008, 13-29; Notz
2020;
Rowbotham 1973, 47; Sayers,
Evans
and Redclift 1987; Vogel 1996).
Although there is besides agreement lots of criticism of Engels’s
formulation, its importance lies in the stress that reproductive
labour such as
housework is a very important aspect of capitalism. It allows a focus
on the
economic dimension of the household where labour-power is reproduced.
Rejecting
interpretations that Engels separates gender oppression from class,
Martha
Gimenez (1987) argues that Engels’s
formulation
should be interpreted dialectically. “Dialectically, that is the
meaning of
Engels’s term, ‘twofold’. To speak of the twofold nature of production
is to
refer, at the metatheoretical level, to its fundamental
moments or
aspects” (Gimenez 1987, 40). Gimenez argues
that
Engels stresses that class and gender oppression have different and
united
dynamics that are interacting, interconnected and entangled through
(re)production and labour.
A key insight from Engels’s The
Origin of the Family, Private Property
and the State for understanding digital labour is that labour
extends
beyond the factory and the office. The political economist of
communication
Dallas W. Smythe (1977) stresses that audience labour is labour that produces attention for advertisements. Consumers
are audience workers who create the value of the advertisement (see Fuchs 2012). Targeted-advertising based
Internet
platforms such as Google and Facebook make profit based on the
analysis of
users’ online behaviour, which results in the collection of big data,
which
allows them to target ads (see Fuchs 2017;
2021). Users of Google and Facebook are
unpaid digital
workers, who produce Google and Facebook’s value. They produce social
relations, content, data, and meta-data that is appropriated by Google
and
Facebook and used for targeting and selling ads. Audience and user
labour are
like housework unpaid forms of productive, value-generating labour
that operate
beyond wage-labour. But housework and user labour are also quite
different (for
a discussion of commonalities and differences of wage-labour,
slave-labour,
housework, and user labour, see Fuchs 2018a).
Housework
produces and reproduces labour power. It is reproductive labour.
Audience and user labour operate as part of entertainment as
reproductive
labour in the household. But audience and user labour also operate
outside the
home in a variety of social spaces via the use of mobile phones,
laptops,
tablets, etc. They facilitate the sale of commodities and the
realisation of
surplus-value, i.e. the generation of profit by commodity sale.
Housework makes
labour-power saleable on the labour commodity. User and audience
labour
contribute to the reproduction of labour-power via
advertising-financed
entertainment. These two forms of labour help selling goods on
commodity
markets by creating the value of ads.
Engels’s The Origin of the Family,
Private Property and the State has laid the foundation for the
critical
comprehension of the extension of the notion of productive labour
beyond
wage-labour and of the extension of the factory and the office into
the
household and onto the Internet.
Digital
capitalism
is based on an international division of digital labour, where a
variety of workers is exploited under a variety of working conditions
in
different countries and working spaces so that transnational digital
corporations accumulate capital. Engels in CWCE
outlines concepts and analyses that can inspire digital labour
analysis in the
21st century. He shows how capital uses technology as
method of
relative surplus-value production. In digital capitalism, digital
technologies
constitute a technological paradigm that advances new forms of
automation and
rationalisation of labour that have resulted in significant
productivity
increases so that more capital can be accumulated in less time. Engels
also
points out the inhumane consequences of absolute surplus-value
production, i.e.
the lengthening of the working day. In digital capitalism, absolute
surplus-value production takes on the form of highly exploitative
Taylorist
work organisation in Chinese hardware assemblage factories owned by
companies
such as Foxconn or Pegatron, where workers toil long hours to produce
the
profits of transnational digital corporations such as Apple, Dell, or
HP.
In digital capitalism, one also finds a
form of absolute surplus-value production in software and other
companies that
employ highly skilled and highly paid engineers, who are incentivised
to spend
long hours and their life in office complexes such as the Googleplex
where the
boundaries between labour/play, working time/leisure time,
office/home,
workers/friends and family blur. The result is that the digital labour
aristocracy works very long hours and has high wages but suffers from
social
poverty, i.e. a lack of work/life-balance, friendships and social life
outside
of the workplace. Digital platform workers are what Engels and Marx
characterised as piece-wage workers. Engels’s concept of social murder
matters
for understanding how in the COVID-19 crisis, the profit imperative
combined
with a lack of protective measures and social distancing in capitalist
corporations put low-paid, low skilled workers at risk of infection
and death.
Engels’s stress on reproductive labour in The
Origin
of the Family, Private Property and the State reminds us that
in
capitalism there are unremunerated unpaid forms of labour, such as
housework
and Facebook usage, that create commodities such as labour-power and
advertising space. In digital capitalism, we find digital houseworkers
who are
unpaid and highly exploited (see Jarrett 2016).
The international division of digital labour means transnational digital
corporations’ global outsourcing of labour in order to maximise
profits. The
question arises what potentials there are for working class struggles
against
exploitation in digital capitalism. The next section addresses this
issue.
CWCE’s chapter 8 “Labour Movements”
analyses the
role of working class struggles in capitalism. In this chapter, Engels
identifies and analyses different types of working class struggles: a)
crime,
b) the destruction of machinery, c) trade unions, and d) political
movements.
Engels stresses that there are different ways of how workers react to
their exploitation. “To escape despair, there are but two ways open to
him [the
worker]; either inward and outward revolt against the bourgeoisie or
drunkenness and general demoralization. And the English operatives are
accustomed to take refuge in both”, which resulted in “hundreds of
uprising
against machinery and the bourgeoisie” (CWCE, 149).
At
the time when Engels wrote CWCE,
struggles of the working class were particularly focused on the
introduction of
the ten hours working day. Engels again and again refers to these
struggles (CWCE, 179, 182-185, 242, 313).
Such
struggles resulted in the introduction of the Ten Hours Bill 1847 that
limited
the working day for women and teenagers to a maximum of ten hours.
Engels sees crime as purely individual reaction and the destruction of
machinery as limited to one single dimension of capital’s rule. He
propagates
the unity of economic class struggles and political class struggles.
He argues
for the “union of Socialism with Chartism, the reproduction of French
Communism
in an English manner”. In digital capitalism, there is a large number
of
different cybercrimes, crime that is committed using digital
technologies such
as the Internet (see Wall 2007 for an
overview
discussion of cybercrime). Many Internet users every day receive spam
and
online scams via e-mails, which are the most widely spread forms of
cybercrime.
Such forms of cybercrime are not the reactions of a disenfranchised
working
class, but highly profitable capitalist businesses.
Machine breaking means the resistance against the introduction of
machinery and “revolts against machinery” (CWCE, 222).
In
industrialising England, machine breaking was known as “Luddism”, a
movement
named after its founder Ned Ludd. “This form of opposition also was
isolated,
restricted to certain localities, and directed against one feature
only of our
present social arrangements” (CWCE, 222).
In
the book The Making of the English Working Class, the Marxist
historian E. P. Thompson (1966) makes a
more
positive assessment of the Luddite movement than Engels (see also Fuchs 2016, 2000-2004). He writes that Luddism
was not a blind
attack on machinery as end-in-itself, but a well-organised movement
that
attacked the machines of capitalists that laid off workers (Thompson
1966, 564). Luddism was a working class
struggle for “a democratic community, in which industrial growth
should be
regulated according to ethical priorities and the pursuit of profit be
subordinated to human needs” (Thompson 1966,
552).
In digital capitalism, one can again and again hear suggestions and see
initiatives that call for stopping to use digital technologies. An
example is
digital detoxing, the conscious choice to stop using digital
technologies for
certain periods of time. The problem of such strategies is that they
often are
technophobic and techno-deterministic. They see digital technologies
as such as
the cause of stress, health problems, depression, loneliness, etc.
They
abstract from the capitalist, class and power relations that shape
contemporary
digital technologies. Digital detox retreats have turned into a new
form of
capital accumulation, where stressed digital workers pay for switching
off
their phones and laptops for a weekend or a week. For example, the
three-day
digital detox retreat at The Detox Barn in Suffolk (UK) costs £415 per
person
“for three nights (Friday – Monday) including all meals, two yoga
sessions,
smoothie demos, guided country walks and guided meditation”[9].
Deceleration, digital detox and digital Luddism are capital
accumulation
strategies. They advance the very cause of the stress and problems
that digital
workers suffer – capitalism.
Engels
“was the first socialist to highlight the importance of trade unions
to the
struggle for socialism, and this fundamental insight was the concrete
corollary
of his historical humanism” (Blackledge
2019, 42).
Trade unions aim at
raising
wages and “protecting the single working man against the tyranny and
neglect of
the bourgeoisie” (CWCE, 223). The strike is
the union’s main
method of struggle by which they harm capitalists whose capital is
“idle as
long as the strike lasted, and his machinery would be rusting” (CWCE, 225).
The capitalist antagonism
between capital and labour is one about the control of the means of
production
and working time. The capitalist wants to make the workers conduct as
much
unpaid labour-time as possible, whereas the workers have the interest
to
control all of their labour-time themselves and not to be controlled
by
capitalists and managers. A strike disrupts labour-time. Workers stop
to work.
Necessary and surplus labour time are both zero. No value is created.
No
commodities are produced. Capitalists make no profit.
Engels writes about the emergence of a “New Unionism” (CWCE, 324),
new trade unions of unskilled workers. These trade unions differed
from the old
unions of skilled workers focused on wage increases because unskilled
workers
often faced unemployment and no wages at all. In digital capitalism,
we need
digital trade unions that support digital workers in uniting in
struggles
against digital capital.
Digital socialism begins and develops through class struggles of digital
workers. The working class has changed. There are a lot of digital
workers in
an international digital division of labour. Class struggles in the
21st
century must look different than in the 19th and 20th centuries, as
the forms
and places of work have changed. Many freelancers work in the digital
industry.
They are not capitalists, but members of the working class. Most of
them only
own a computer as a means of production, no monetary capital. They do
not hire
other workers either. They work sporadically and precariously. And
they are
very difficult to reach and organize in trade unions. Co-working
spaces
provided free or cheaply by unions create spaces where digital workers
come
together and can be social spaces and starting points for union
organising.
Traditional
trade unions have problems with the representation and organisation of
atypical
workers such as freelancers. Some unions do not even intend to
represent
freelancers because they consider them to be capitalists. As the world
of work
has changed, trade unions and their strategies must change if they
want to
advance the interests of the working class. It is of particular
importance that
trade unions as well as left, socialist and communist parties and
movements
deal with precarious work, domestic work, unemployment, consumer work,
public
work, Facebook user work, digital work, digital surveillance, etc. and
defend
and represent these forms of work.
With the
convergence of production and consumption, some consumer issues have
become
labour rights issues. Trade unions and left, socialist and communist
parties
and movements should therefore consider digital consumer issues as
labour
rights issues and start to join forces with consumer protection
associations.
The unions have lost influence and
power, which means that the power of capital has been strengthened in
class
struggles. If the labour movement and trade unions do not succeed in
engaging
and organising on issues such as digital work, domestic work, unpaid
work,
freelance work, crowdsourcing, platform work, consumer work, work of
internet
users, privacy, digital surveillance, consumer protection, slave
labour, etc.,
and if they do not see these issues as key to labour struggles, these
movements
commit suicide. To challenge the power of global capital requires the
global
networking of the working class and the internationalization of trade
unions,
left movements, socialist parties and trade union membership.
Class struggles are of course already
taking place in digital capitalism. One example is strikes by
Uber-riders. They
are digital workers exploited by the Uber corporation, which controls
the Uber
app as a means of production. In a lawsuit in Britain it was confirmed
that
Uber-drivers have the legal status of workers.
Worker
self-control means that the workers gain control over the app and its
source
code. For example, if the digital courier workers unionise with
software
engineers, an alternative app could be created. A strike by digital
workers at
Uber, Deliveroo, etc. would then consist of, for example, using the
union app
for one week instead of the capitalist app and damaging the capitalist
companies during this period, for example to push through demands for
a minimum
wage of 15 Euros per hour for platform workers. Such a strike is a new
form of
class struggle in and against digital capital.
In digital capitalism, strikes need to
add new digital dimensions of struggles in order to be effective. On
the one
hand, given that lots of news consumption and everyday communication
takes
place via social media, unions and labour movements should be present
on social
media and should mobilise and organise via social media and
communicate their
goals using hashtags, video platforms, social networking sites,
messenger apps,
blogs, memes, digital images, digital animations, etc. On the other
hand,
digital corporations such as Google, Facebook, and Amazon accumulate
capital
online, which is why digital strikes against such companies should
make use of
users-boycotts’, which helps disrupting these corporations
profit-making and
allows putting pressure on them when making demands. An example of the
digital
strike is Adbuster’s #OccupySiliconValley, a one-day digital strike
against
Facebook, Amazon, Apple, and Google that took place in September 2018.
It
called on users not to use these platforms for one day. Given that
online usage
of platforms such as Facebook and Google is not just consumption but
also
labour, a Facebook- and Google-boycott is also a labour strike. The
digital
workers put their eyeballs to rest or direct them elsewhere, which
disrupts
digital value creation. The campaign call read:
Big Tech competes for one thing: our attention. They exploit our basic human instincts in the pursuit of unprecedented financial and cultural control. […] You can turn September 17th into DO NOTHING DAY [….] Partake in a one-day embargo against tech altogether. […] On September 17th, each one of us, in our own sweet way, will participate in a global takedown of Big Tech! […] Make the Internet ours again[10].
In
respect
to political struggles, Engels was a supporter of the Chartist
movement, a political reform movement that struggled for suffrage and
was
associated with the English working class movement. Engels writes that
the
Chartists “wish to put a proletarian law in the place of the legal
fabric of
the bourgeoisie” (CWCE, 235). Chartism was
for Engels a
“class movement” that aimed at “Chartist democracy” (CWCE, 242).
Already
in this early work by Engels, it becomes evident that he did not
understand communism as a totalitarian state but as a democratic
socialist
society. Consequently, Marx and Engels in the Manifesto of the
Communist Party
spoke of communism as “the struggle for democracy”[11]
(Marx and Engels 1848a, 481).
The
struggle for the reduction of the
working day is the practical combination of economic and political
struggles.
In England, the 1847 Ten Hours Bill was the result of the combination
of the socialist,
the union and the Chartist movement. In the 1860s, the First
International, in
which Marx and Engels were key figures, formulated the demand of
“eight hours
work as the legal limit of the working day” (International
Working
Men’s Association 1868, 5).
In
1919, the International Labour
Organization passed the Hours of Work (Industry) Convention and in
1930 the
Hours of Work (Commerce and Offices) Convention that defines the
standard
working week as not exceeding 48 hours per week and eight hours a day.
In 2020,
52 countries had passed the first convention and 30 the second. Given
there are
193 member states of the United Nations, it is evident that only a
rather low
number of countries has signed these international conventions. The
prevalence
of temporary work, zero hours contracts, part-time work, freelance
labour, etc.
shows that labour-time remains a key dimension of the class antagonism
between
capital and labour in the 21st century.
In
2020, the digital productive forces
are developed to a high degree so that labour-time could be
significantly
reduced and everyone could work fewer hours but lead a better life.
But digital
technologies are embedded into what Marx and Engels termed the
antagonism
between the productive forces and the relations of production.
In
the Communist Manifesto, they speak of the “revolt of modern productive
forces against modern conditions of production” in capitalist society
“that has
conjured up such gigantic means of production and of exchange” and “is
like the
sorcerer, who is no longer able to control the powers of the nether
world whom
he has called up by his spells” (Marx and
Engels
1848b, 489). In digital capitalism, the antagonism between the
digital
productive forces and capitalist relations of production takes on the
form of
an antagonism between digital capital and the digital commons. On the
one hand,
there are new forms of capital accumulation in the digital industries
that
combine a variety of digital commodities and digital labour. On the
other hand,
there are new forms of the digital commons – such as not-for-profit
online
platforms, non-commercial news media, Wikipedia, the free and open
source
software, non-commercial Creative Commons, platform co-operatives, the
free
software movement, radical open access, etc. – that go beyond digital
capital
and practically question capital accumulation. The antagonism between
the
digital machines and class relations has advanced the radical
asymmetrical
distribution of labour-time. Whereas some workers are highly stressed,
have no
leisure time and work very long hours, others are unemployed,
underemployed, or
precarious workers. The
productive
forces enable a substantial reduction of the standard working day that
allows a
more symmetrical distribution of labour time and a good life for all.
Establishing a reduction of the working week without wage cuts
requires class
struggles for radical reforms of labour legislation. Just like the
labour
movement struggled for first for the ten-hours- and then for the
eight-hours-working day, in digital capitalism we need struggles for
the
five-hours-working day and a four-day-working week with full wage
compensation.
Such struggles point towards a post-scarcity society, in which digital
technologies
are used to minimise necessary labour time and maximise free time and
the good
life for all.
Writing
in 1845, Engels says that a
“mass of Acts for enclosing and cultivating
commons is passed at every session of Parliament” (CWCE, 287).
Communism
“does away with all class antagonisms” (CWCE, 301).
In
the early phase of capitalism, common land was enclosed and peasants
were
forced into wage-labour. Marx (1867) terms
this phase
primitive accumulation. But primitive accumulation never ended. It
continues in
the form of imperialism, attempts of capital to make use of violence
and other
means for turning non-commodified spheres of society and nature into
realms of capital
accumulation. That is why digital capital seeks to colonise
non-capitalist
spaces such as the digital commons and turn them into spheres of
digital
capital accumulation. Engels pointed out that non-capitalist
alternatives are
possible and needed. For example, in the realm of media and education
he argues
that radical media and education are important intellectual means of
struggle.
He saw the Chartist newspaper Northern
Star as “The only sheet which reports all the movements of the
proletariat”
(CWCE, 232). He stressed the
importance of
educational institutions such as the Chartist institutions where “the
children
receive a purely proletarian education, free from all the influences
of the
bourgeoisie” and one finds “reading-rooms” with “proletarian journals
and
books” (CWCE, 245).
We
need concrete utopias of digital
socialism. I see two potentials: On the one hand, the renewal of the
movement of
co-operatives and self-managed companies in the form of platform
co-operatives,
i.e. Internet platforms that are self-managed by users and digital
workers. On
the other hand, the creation of public Internet platforms through a
network of
public media.
Examples
of platform co-operatives are
the music platform Resonate, Fairbnb (an alternative to Airbnb),
Taxiapp (an
alternative to Uber), the photo platform Stocksy and the cooperation
platform
Loomio (Fuchs 2021, chapters 12, 14, & 15).
Many
platform co=operatives do not make it from concept to reality and many
soon
disappear again. Those that do exist usually remain small and
insignificant, so
they cannot challenge the digital capital. The Marxist social
scientist Marisol
Sandoval (2019) analyses how some of the
platform
co-operatives use the capitalist language and logic of “shareholders”,
“profits”, “investments”, “creators”, “entrepreneurs”, “innovation”,
etc., thus
displacing radical politics.
Socialism
is neither an app nor a
platform. It cannot be downloaded from the Internet or clicked on a
mobile
phone. It is not enough to organise platforms as co-operatives. In
order to
survive and create a better society, platform co-operatives must
politicise
themselves and act as part of radical social movements that fight
collectively
and politically against capitalism and for socialism. Socialism is not
an app
and not a platform, but a political movement. Sandoval (2016a;
2016b; 2019)
argues
that platform co-operatives should play an important role in this
movement and
that we need class struggle co-operatives. By class-struggle
co-operatives
Sandoval means that co-operatives become parts of socialist movements
fighting
for redistribution, capital taxation and socialism. They are part of
what
Bhaskar Sunkara (2019) calls class-struggle
social
democracy, whereby social democracy is to be understood in the sense
of
Luxembourg as a democratic socialist movement and party.
In
order to prevent a new fascism it is
necessary to defend and renew democracy. Public media should play an
important
role in this. They are non-capitalist because they are not
profit-oriented. And
they can only act critically and as public media if they are not
controlled by
the state, i.e. they are not state media. The strengthening of
non-capitalist
media is an aspect of the class struggle in so far as the power of the
capitalist media is pushed back. But today we see that right-wing
forces are
attacking the public media and would like to abolish them. One
strategy against
this is the renewal of the public media in the Internet age.
There
are initiatives like Public Open
Space (https://public-open-space.eu)
and discussions about the need for public media and international
networks of
public media as operators of public internet platforms. For example, a
public
YouTube, jointly operated by the BBC, ARD, ORF, etc., on which the
archive
material of the public media is offered with Creative Commons licenses
for
remixing for non-commercial purposes (Fuchs
2017c; 2018b; 2018d).
Or a new
edition of the legendary debate format Club 2 of the Austrian
Broadcasting
Corporation (ORF) in the form of an Internet-based Club 2.0, in order
to
counter the lack of debate culture that prevails in mediatised,
digital
capitalism. The principle of Club 2 was that it was a live discussion
without
censorship, without advertising and with open air time. Club 2 was a
public
sphere.
In
today's highly accelerated capitalism
there is hardly any time and space for complex arguments and debates.
The
acceleration logic of capital has also colonized culture, leading to
the
acceleration and boulevardisation of the public sphere. More and more
experiences are squeezed into short time spans, leaving hardly any
time for
reflection and reflected discussion. The result is the
boulevardisation of the
media. Reality TV is one example of this. In my opinion, Hartmut Rosa
(2013) correctly points out the alienated
aspects of
acceleration. It is crucial in this respect to see that acceleration
under
capitalism is driven by the logic of accumulation.
Club
2.0 is the digital public sphere in
the age of user-generated content and social media (Fuchs
2017c; 2018b; 2018d).
We
need to strengthen and update the independence of public media from
the
state and capital and empower them to act as operators of digital
platforms on the
Internet and to use these platforms for further developing public
service
media’s remits.
Concrete
utopias of digital socialism
need concrete initiatives and projects that should be part of broader
movements
and struggles for socialism and the rescue and strengthening of the
commons and
the public sphere.
In
CWCE, Engels gave
significant attention
to working class struggles. One can draw important lessons from
Engels’s
insights for the analysis of digital working class struggles. Engels
stresses
the importance of trade unions, strikes, and radical political reforms
as
aspects of class struggles. In digital capitalism, we need new forms,
strategies and methods of trade unions and class struggle. 21st
century society trade unions need to take serious housework,
freelancers, the
unemployed, platform labour and other forms of digital labour, the
tendency of
production and consumption to converge, digital surveillance, etc. In
digital
capitalism, many consumer rights issues are labour rights issues. In digital capitalism, strikes
need to add
new digital dimensions of struggles in order to be effective. There
are two
implications: First, class struggles and strikes should make use of
digital
platforms as means of organisation, mobilisation and communication.
Second,
strikes should also take place online and disrupt value production
on digital
platforms in order to exert digital power against digital capital.
Engels
stresses that questions of labour time are an important aspect of
working class
struggles. In 21st-century digital capitalism, the digital
productive forces
are so highly developed that the struggle for a five hour-working
day and a
four hour-working week is a realistic and necessary demand for
improving the
quality of life of the working class that today suffers from the
precarity
caused by the antagonism between the digital productive forces and
the
capitalist relations of production. Engels stressed the need for
alternatives
to capital and capitalism. In digital society, platform
co-operatives, digital
commons projects and public service Internet platforms are concrete
digital
utopias that point beyond digital capital(ism). Such projects and
demands to
implement and support them should be part of struggles for a good
life for all
and 21st century socialism.
Engels’ 200th
anniversary is an
excellent occasion for the analysis of life and the conditions of the
working
class in digital capitalism. This article contributed to this task by
dealing
with the question: How relevant are Friedrich Engels’s works in the
age of
digital capitalism?
This paper showed that Friedrich Engels’s works remain highly relevant
in 21st century society and can inform the critical
analysis of
digital capitalism, technology and society, computational social
science,
digital positivism, digital labour, digital labour struggles, and the
digital
commons.
It is a mistake to assume that Engels is to blame for Stalinism and was
the first vulgariser of Marx. But it is also an error to assume that
his works
are flawless. There are problematic, deterministic formulations in his
works.
But by and large he has stressed the importance of class struggles in
and
against capitalism and that the basic social law of society is that
humans make
their own history based on and shaped by given conditions. Engels did
not
formulate a theory of the automatic collapse of capitalism. Scientific
socialism is not a natural science theory of society, but an
anti-positivist
dialectical social analysis the uses the dialectics of subject/object,
agency/structures, practices/conditions, experience/reason, empirical
research/social theory, chance/necessity, discontinuity/continuity,
disorder/order, diversity/unity, individual/society, local/global,
spontaneity/organisation,
etc.
Let us summarise the main findings of this article:
·
Scientific socialism:
Scientific socialism doesn’t mean that society is governed by
mechanical laws, but that socialist research studies society based on
the
combination of critical social theory and critical empirical social
research.
For Engels just like for Marx, there is a difference between natural
dialectics
and societal dialectics. The basic law of society is that humans make
their own
history under given conditions. In class society, class and social
struggles
are the processes, by which humans make their own history.
·
The critique of computational social science
as digital positivism:
In
the
contemporary social sciences, computational social sciences have
emerged as a
dominant paradigm that attracts lots of attention, support, and
funding. Engels understood scientific
socialism as a critique
of positivism. Computational social science is a digital positivism
that poses the
danger of turning the social
sciences into administrative, instrumental, positivist research that
supports
domination and exploitation. It neglects that qualitative features of
society
such as motivations, norms, moral values, feelings, ideologies,
experiences,
love, death, freedom, or (in)justice that cannot be reduced to
quantities and
computation.
·
The international division of digital labour:
Digital
capitalism
is based on an international division of digital labour, where a
variety of workers is exploited under a variety of working conditions
in
different countries and working spaces so that transnational digital
corporations accumulate capital. The international division of digital
labour
means transnational digital corporations’ global outsourcing of labour
in order
to maximise profits. Engels in The
Condition
of the Working Class in England outlines concepts and analyses
that can
inspire digital labour analysis in the 21st century.
·
The antagonism between the digital productive
forces and the capitalist relations of production:
Engels
shows
how capital uses technology as method of relative surplus-value
production. In digital capitalism, digital technologies constitute a
technological paradigm that advances new forms of automation and
rationalisation of labour that have resulted in significant
productivity increases
so that more capital can be accumulated in less time. Digital
capitalism is
shaped by the antagonism between the digital productive forces and the
capitalist relations of production. In
21st century digital capitalism, the digital productive
forces are
so highly developed that the struggle for a five hour-working day
and a four
hour-working week is a realistic and necessary demand for improving
the quality
of life of the working class that today suffers from the precarity
caused by
the antagonism between the digital productive forces and the
capitalist
relations of production. Engels stresses that questions of labour
time are an
important aspect of working class struggles.
·
The exploitation of digital labour:
Engels
points
out the inhumane consequences of absolute surplus-value production,
i.e.
the lengthening of the working day. In digital capitalism, absolute
surplus-value production takes on the form of highly exploitative
Taylorist
work organisation in Chinese hardware assemblage factories owned by
companies
such as Foxconn or Pegatron, where workers toil long hours to produce
the
profits of transnational digital corporations such as Apple, Dell, or
HP. In
digital capitalism, one also finds a form of absolute surplus-value
production
in software and other companies that employ highly skilled and highly
paid
engineers, who are incentivised to spend long hours and their life in
office
complexes such as the Googleplex where the boundaries between
labour/play,
working time/leisure time, office/home, workers/friends and family
blur. The
result is that the digital labour aristocracy works very long hours
and has
high wages but suffers from social poverty, i.e. a lack of
work/life-balance,
friendships and social life outside of the workplace. Digital platform
workers
are what Engels and Marx characterised as piece-wage workers.
·
The social murder of workers in the COVID-19
crisis:
Engels’s
concept
of social murder matters for understanding how in the COVID-19 crisis,
the
profit imperative combined with a lack of protective measures and
social
distancing in capitalist corporations put low-paid, low skilled
workers at risk
of infection and death. Engels’s stress on reproductive labour in The Origin of the Family, Private
Property
and the State reminds us that in capitalism there are
unremunerated unpaid
forms of labour, such as housework and Facebook usage, that create
commodities
such as labour-power and advertising space. In digital capitalism, we
find
digital houseworkers who are unpaid and highly exploited.
·
The
Condition
of the Working Class in England (CWCE):
In
CWCE, Engels gave
significant attention
to working class struggles. One can draw important lessons from
Engels’s
insights for the analysis of digital working class struggles.
·
Trade unions in the digital age:
Engels
stresses
the importance of trade unions, strikes, and radical political reforms
as aspects of class struggles. In digital capitalism, we need new
forms,
strategies and methods of trade unions and class struggle. 21st
century society trade unions need to take serious housework,
freelancers, the
unemployed, platform labour and other forms of digital labour, the
tendency of
production and consumption to converge, digital surveillance, etc. In
digital
capitalism, many consumer rights issues are labour rights issues.
·
Digital
working
class struggles:
In digital capitalism, strikes need to add new
digital dimensions of struggles in order to be effective. There are
two
implications: First, class struggles and strikes should make use of
digital
platforms as means of organisation, mobilisation and communication.
Second,
strikes should also take place online and disrupt value production on
digital
platforms in order to exert digital power against digital capital.
·
Alternatives
to
digital capitalism:
Engels stressed the need for alternatives to
capital and capitalism. In digital society, platform co-operatives,
digital
commons projects and public service Internet platforms are concrete
digital utopias
that point beyond digital capital(ism). Such projects and demands to
implement
and support them should be part of struggles for a good life for all
and 21st
century socialism.
In
The Housing Question, Engels
(1872, 324-325) argues:
And it is precisely this industrial revolution which has raised the productive power of human labour to such a high level that – for the first time in the history of mankind – the possibility exists, given a rational division of labour among all, of producing not only enough for the plentiful consumption of all members of society and for an abundant reserve fund, but also of leaving each individual sufficient leisure so that what is really worth preserving in historically inherited culture – science, art, forms of intercourse, etc. – may not only be preserved but converted from a monopoly of the ruling class into the common property of the whole of society, and may be further developed.
Computing
has
helped creating foundations for a highly productive post-scarcity
socialist
society, where wealth for all is possible and culture is the common
property of
the whole of society. Writing in the 19th century, Engels
wrote of
science, art (and more general forms of intercourse) as aspects of
culture that
in socialism benefit all. Today, he would also include digital
technologies
such as the Internet and would demand the creation of digital commons.
If
Engels were alive today, he would criticise all digital capital
accumulation
models and argue that digital technologies shouldn’t be capital and
commodities
but common properties available without payment to the whole of
society and
benefiting everyone. Engels would certainly support the creation of a
public
service and commons-based Internet (see Fuchs
2021,
chapters 14 & 15).
200 years after Friedrich Engels’s birth, capitalism
is alive, but Marx and Engels are not dead. They are ghosts that keep
on
haunting capitalism in the digital age in the form of class struggles
and
critical class analysis. Engels is a representative of a “dynamic,
humanist,
and creative” (Blackledge 2019, 242)
critique of
the political economy of capitalism. Engels’s 200th
birthday reminds
us of the class character of digital capitalism and that we need
critical
digital social science as a new form of scientific socialism.
Becker, Markus et al. 2020.
Corona in
the Slaughterhouse: The High Price of Cheap Meat. Der Spiegel, 26
June 2020, https://www.spiegel.de/international/business/corona-in-the-slaughterhouse-the-high-price-of-cheap-meat-a-ad16d0df-c1c8-4f82-93df-573fdc2c8bd6
Bellafante, Ginia. 2020. “We Didn’t Sign Up For This”: Amazon Workers on the Front Lines. The New York Times, 3 April 2020, https://www.nytimes.com/2020/04/03/nyregion/coronavirus-nyc-chris-smalls-amazon.html
Boltanski, Luc and Ève Chiapello. 2005. The New Spirit of Capitalism. London: Verso.
Carver, Terrell. 1990. Friedrich
Engels: His Life and Thought.
New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Carver, Terrell. 1983. Marx and Engels Their Intellectual Relationship. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books.
Carver, Terrell. 1981. Engels. A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deutsche Welle. 2020a. Germany: Former
Abattoir Worker ‘Heard Colleagues Cry at Night’. Deutsche Welle, 25 June 2020.
https://www.dw.com/en/germany-former-abattoir-worker-heard-colleagues-crying-at-night/a-53943595
Deutsche Welle 2020b. Germany: Romanian
Workers Reveal Dire Conditions at Slaughterhouses. Deutsche Welle, 3
July
2020. https://www.dw.com/en/germany-meat-industry-conditions/a-54033187
Engels, Friedrich. 1894. Letter to Borgius. 25 January 1894. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1894/letters/94_01_25.htm
Fuchs, Christian. 2021. Social Media:
A Critical Introduction.
London:
Sage. Third edition.
Fuchs,
Christian.
2020a. Communication and
Capitalism. A Critical Theory. London: University of Westminster
Press. https://doi.org/10.16997/book45
Fuchs, Christian. 2020b. Everyday Life and Everyday
Communication in Coronavirus Capitalism. tripleC:
Communication, Capitalism & Critique 18
(1):
375-399. DOI: https://doi.org/10.31269/triplec.v18i1.1167
Fuchs, Christian. 2018a.
Capitalism,
Patriarchy, Slavery, and Racism in the Age of Digital Capitalism and
Digital
Labour. Critical Sociology
44
(4-5): 677-702.
Fuchs, Christian. 2018b. Digitale Demokratie und
Öffentlich-Rechtliche
Medien. In ORF Public Value
Studie
2017/2018: Der Auftrag: Demokratie, 94-138. Wien: ORF. https://zukunft.orf.at/show_content.php?sid=147&pvi_id=1986&pvi_medientyp=t&oti_tag=studie
Fuchs, Christian. 2018c. Industry 4.0: The Digital German Ideology. tripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique 16 (1): 280-289. DOI: https://doi.org/10.31269/triplec.v16i1.1010
Fuchs, Christian. 2018d. The
Online Advertising Tax as the Foundation
of a Public Service Internet. London: University of Westminster
Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.16997/book23
Fuchs,
Christian.
2017b. Social Media: A
Critical Introduction. London: Sage. Second edition.
Fuchs, Christian. 2017c.
Towards the
Public Service Internet as Alternative to the Commercial Internet. ORF Texte No. 20 –
Öffentlich-Rechtliche
Qualität im Diskurs, 43-50. Vienna: ORF.
Republication: Fuchs, Christian. 2018. Towards the Public Service Internet as Alternative to the Commercial Internet. In Public Open Space: Zur Zukunft öffentlich-rechtlicher Medien, ed. Konrad Mitschka and Klaus Unterberger, 301-307. Vienna: Facultas.
Fuchs,
Christian.
2014. Social Media: A
Critical
Introduction. London: Sage. First edition.
Fülberth, Georg. 2018. Friedrich
Engels. Köln:
PapyRossa.
García-Hodges, Ahiza, Jo Ling Kent, and Ezra Kaplan. 2020. Amazon Warehouse in Minnesota Had More Than 80 COVID-19 Cases. NBC News, 24 June 2020, https://www.nbcnews.com/tech/tech-news/amazon-warehouse-minnesota-had-more-80-covid-19-cases-n1231937
Harvey,
David.
2005. A Brief History of
Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Horkheimer, Max. 1947. Eclipse of Reason. New York: Continuum.
International Working Men’s Association. 1868. Resolutions of the Congress of Geneva, 1866, and the Congress of Brussels,1868. London: Westminster Printing Company.
Jarrett,
Kylie. 2016. Feminism, Labour and Digital Media: The Digital Housewife. New York, NY: Routledge.
Kopf, Eike. 2017. Marxismus
ohne
Engels? Köln: PapyRossa.
Lazer, David et al. 2009, Computational Social Science. Science 323: 721-723.
Levine, Norman. 1975. The Tragic Deception. Marx Contra Engels. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and Class Consciousness. London: Merlin.
Marx, Karl. 1867. Capital. Volume I. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1857/58. Grundrisse. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl 1852.
The
Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte. In Marx
&
Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 11, 99-197. London:
Lawrence & Wishart.
Mayer, Gustav. 1935. Friedrich Engels. A Biography. London: Chapman & Hall.
McLellan, David. 1993.
Introduction.
In Friedrich Engels: The
Condition of the
Working Class in England, ix-xx. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Rowbotham, Sheila. 1973. Woman’s Consciousness, Man’s World. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Sandoval, Marisol. 2019. Entrepreneurial Activism? Platform Cooperativism
Between Subversion and Co-optation. Critical
Sociology, DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0896920519870577
Schmidt, Alfred. 1971. The Concept of Nature in Marx. London: NLB.
Students & Scholars Against Corporate Misbehaviour (SACOM). 2011. iSlave Behind the iPhone: Foxconn Workers in Central China. http://sacom.hk/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/2011-iSlave-Behind-the-iPhone-Foxconn-Workers-in-Central-China.pdf (accessed on 21 October 2019).
Thompson, Edward P. 1966. The Making of the English Working Class. New York: Vintage Books.
Wall, David S.
2007. Cybercrime: The
Transformation of
Crime in the Information Age. Cambridge:
Polity.
Zimmermann, Clemens. 2020. Die Lage der arbeitenden
Klasse in England. In Friedrich
Engels:
Ein Gespenst geht um in Euopa. Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung
2020, ed. Lars Bluma,
70-83. Remscheid: Bergischer Verlag.
Christian Fuchs
Christian Fuchs is a critical theorist and the co-editor of tripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique (http://www.triple-c.at). http://fuchsc.net, @fuchschristian
[1] Übersetzung aus dem Deutschen [CF]: „die Entfremdung des Menschen von dem Menschen“
[2] Data
source: ILO
World Employment and Social Outlook, http://www.ilo.org/wesodata
[3] Amazon Inc.,
SEC filings,
form 10-Q for the quarterly period ending 31 March 2020, https://ir.aboutamazon.com/sec-filings
[4] Data source: Yahoo! Finance, https://finance.yahoo.com/quote/AMZN
[5] Data source:
Forbes 2000
list for the year 2020, https://www.forbes.com/global2000,
accessed on 11 July 2020.
[6] Forbes World’s Billionaires List for 2020, https://www.forbes.com/billionaires/
[7] Data source: https://toennies.de/en/home/,
accessed on 11 July 2020.
[8] Data source:
Forbes
World’s Billionaires List for the year 2020, https://www.forbes.com/billionaires/,
accessed on 11 July 2020.
[9] https://queenofretreats.com/retreats/the-detox-barn-suffolk-uk/,
accessed on 12 July 2020.
[10] http://abillionpeople.org/occupy-silicon-valley/,
accessed on 11 July 2020.
[11] Translation from German: „die Erkämpfung der Demokratie“