M. N. Roy and the Frankfurt School: Socialist Humanism and the Critical Analysis of Communication, Culture, Technology, Fascism and Nationalism
Christian Fuchs
University of Westminster, London, UK, http://fuchs.uti.at, @fuchschristian
Abstract: Manabendra Nath Roy (1887-1954) was the founder of the Communist Parties of Mexico and India and a socialist-humanist philosopher. In the Western world, his works are today widely ignored and forgotten. This article introduces some philosophical aspects of Roy’s thought. It engages with foundations of his theory and shows its relevance for the study of communication, culture, technology, the human being, fascism, and nationalism. Frankfurt School thinkers such as Theodor W. Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Herbert Marcuse, and Erich Fromm were interested in similar topics to Roy. This article also compares the approach of Roy and the Frankfurt School. It shows parallels between Roy and the first generation of the Frankfurt School with respect to themes such as the dialectic of technology and society, the dialectic of the Enlightenment, fascism, nationalism, and authoritarianism. In the age of new nationalisms and authoritarian capitalism, global environmental crises, capitalist crisis, and the digital crisis, socialist-humanist theories such as M. N. Roy’s can inspire struggles for a humanist and socialist society as antidotes to the acceleration and deepening of the three crises.
Keywords: M. N. Roy, Manabendra Nath Roy, socialist humanism,
Marxist
humanism, Karl Marx, Marxism, communication, culture, technology,
ideology, fascism, nationalism, authoritarianism, liberalism,
capitalism,
socialism, Frankfurt School, Theodor W. Adorno, Max Horkheimer,
Herbert
Marcuse, Erich Fromm, Georg Lukács, Rosa Luxemburg, Eric J. Hobsbawm,
August
Thalheimer
Image source: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Mn_roy2.jpg
[Public domain]
This
article asks: How
can M. N. Roy’s radical Marxist humanism inform the critical study of
communication, culture, technology, the human being, fascism, and
nationalism?
What commonalities are there between Roy’s approach and Frankfurt
School
critical theory?
Manabendra Nath (M. N.) Roy
(1887-1954) was a Marxist-humanist thinker and politician. As a
humanist he
opposed Stalinism, Gandhism and the Indian National Congress’ and its
leader
Subhas Chandra Bose’s political position towards Hitler and the Nazis,
which
placed him outside the mainstream of both the communist and the
anti-colonial
movements, contributing to “the forgetting of M. N. Roy” and his being
“lost to
the historical record” (Manjapra 2010, xiv).
He
experienced turmoil, wars and transitions in the 20th
century and
was a contemporary of Frankfurt School thinkers such as Theodor W.
Adorno, Max
Horkheimer, and Herbert Marcuse. Coming from India and spending
sixteen years
(1915-1931) in countries such as the USA, Mexico, Germany, Uzbekistan,
France,
Luxembourg, and China (see Ray 2016a), he
experienced
capitalism and colonialism in various parts of the world.
Both
Roy and the Frankfurt School were
inspired by Marx and humanism and were interested in topics such as
the human
being, technology, culture, communication, ideology, liberalism,
fascism,
authoritarianism, and nationalism. Roy wrote his book Revolution and Counter-Revolution in China in the late 1920s while
connected to the Frankfurt Institute for School Research (Manjapra
2010, xiii, 70, 84, 91 [footnote 27]). In
Germany, Roy and August Thalheimer became close friends and the former
conversed in communist circles with the likes of Karl Korsch, Georg
Lukács,
Eduard Fuchs, Willi Münzberg, Franz Mehring, and Felix Weil (Manjapra
2010, 39-40; 67-70). The latter funded the
founding of the Institute for Social Research.
Subhrajit Bhattacharya (2016, 1432)
points out that Roy and Horkheimer at the same time in the 1930s
“sought to
understand the regression of ‘civilisation’ in the light of
philosophy, one in
an Indian prison, another in his exile years in America”. Both Roy and
the
Frankfurt School took a critical interdisciplinary approach that
combined
political economy, philosophy, sociology, psychoanalysis, and cultural
criticism. It
is interesting to compare the approaches
of Roy and the first generation of the Frankfurt School respecting the
themes
of the human being, technology, culture/communication, ideology,
liberalism,
fascism, authoritarianism, and nationalism.
As an
introduction,
some aspects of Roy’s biography will now be discussed (for details see
Manjapra 2010; Roy S.
1997; Tarkunde 1982).
Roy came
from a Brahmin
family in Bengal. He became a “full-blooded [Indian] nationalist” (Roy 1942, iii) who was convinced that Indian
culture was
superior to Western culture and determined to organise an armed
revolution
against the British rule of India. Observers identify three stages in
Roy’s
political development: He “started as an ardent nationalist, became an
equally
ardent communist and ended as a creatively active Radical Humanist” (Tarkunde 1982, v).
After the
first phase
in his political development Roy, in the second stage, became a
communist when
he went abroad during the First World War. Roy was a founder of the
Mexican
Communist Party in 1917 and the Communist Party of India in the 1920s.
While
staying abroad in the USA and Mexico he gave up the belief that there
was a
progressive element in nationalism and embraced aspects of Western
culture (Roy S. 1987, 1-13). In the 1920s, he
was a member of the
Communist International (Comintern)’s Presidium.
At the
Second Congress
of the Comintern in 1920, Lenin (1920)
presented Theses on the
National and Colonial
Questions. Lenin argued that the “entire [communist] policy on
the national
and the colonial questions should rest primarily on a closer union of
the
proletarians and the working masses of all nations and countries for a
joint
revolutionary struggle to overthrow the landowners and the
bourgeoisie” (1920, 146). Roy (1920)
presented
Supplementary Theses on the
National and
Colonial Question that were more detailed than Lenin’s theses
and resulted
in Lenin’s taking up and agreeing with Roy’s inputs. In his theses,
Roy (1920) argued that European capitalism
“depends on control
of extensive colonial markets and a broad field of opportunities for
exploitation” in order to counter overproduction, that the
“super-profits made
in the colonies form one of the main sources of the resources of
contemporary
capitalism”, and that therefore the “Communist International must
enter into
much closer connection with the revolutionary forces that are at
present
participating in the overthrow of imperialism in the politically and
economically oppressed countries”.
Roy was expelled from the Comintern
in 1929.
He was close to Bukharin, whom Stalin wanted to get rid of, and
supported
anti-Stalinist Marxist movements such as the Communist Party of
Germany (Opposition)
(KPO), whose leader August Thalheimer was Roy’s friend and ally. Both
Thalheimer and Roy were part of the International Communist
Opposition.
Communists around Thalheimer and Heinrich Brandler opposed the
Stalinist
position that the social democrats were the main enemy of the working
class.
Stalinists described social democrats as “social fascists”, and did
not focus
enough on the critique of Nazi-fascism. Members of the Communist
opposition
movement such as Thalheimer argued for a united front of social
democrats and
communists against Nazi-fascism. Roy wrote for the KPO’s publications
and found
the notion of the united front of the exploited and oppressed feasible
for
struggles in the colonies (see Roy 1929a; 1929b). In the late 1920s, Stalin and his
followers in
the Comintern such as Otto Wille Kuusinen disagreed with Roy’s
assessment that
the “nationalist bourgeoisie” in the colonies was compromising with
imperialism
but rather claimed that “the Indian bourgeoisie was brutally
suppressed by Imperialism”
(Roy 1943, 48-49).
Consequently, Stalinists started to
oppose Roy,
which resulted in his expulsion from the Comintern (see Ray
2016b). The Stalinists accused the likes of Thalheimer,
Brandler, and Roy
of “Luxemburgism” (Manjapra 2010, 43-44;
70-71; 86-87),
which, given Rosa Luxemburg’s fusion of socialism, Marxism, and
humanism, Roy
and his comrades did not take as an insult but as confirmation that
they were
true communists. Roy (1943, 47) argues that
the
Communist International’s failed assumption that “Social Democracy was
a
greater enemy of revolution than Fascism” resulted in the Comintern
helping
“Fascism to capture power in Germany”. Roy argues that it was a grave
mistake
that Soviet Minister of Foreign Affairs Molotov “held British
Imperialism
responsible for the war and thus, by implication, exonerated Fascism”
(Roy 1943, 59-60).
Orthodox Marxists have
characterised
socialism as the ideology of the working class, which implies the need
for
dictatorship. They forgot that for Marx the interest of the working
class
“coincided with the interest of the entire society” (Roy
1943,
72), which is why socialism and Marxism are “the philosophy of
the
progressive mankind. The world can be reconstructed as a home of
freedom and
culture only along the lines indicated by Marxism. Therefore,
Communism has
come to its own. It has become the future of mankind, its heritage” (73). For Roy, the Soviet system wasn’t
communist. He
argued that a true form of communism as radical-democratic humanism
remains the
important political goal and interest of humanity.
In his third, humanist phase, Roy
combined
Marxism and humanism. In the 1930s, he joined the Congress Party,
where he was
active in the socialist faction. He broke with Congress during World
World II
over the question of how the party should position itself towards
Nazi-fascism
and the Allied powers. Roy argued that fascism was the world’s
greatest danger
and for the support of the Allies. Others in Congress, such as Gandhi,
said
that there should only be support on the condition of Indian
independence.
Gandhi saw Roy as his “enemy number one” (Roy S.
1987, 17),
while Roy characterised Gandhi as “the patron saint of [Indian]
nationalism” (Roy S. 1987, 67; Roy
1968, 29).
In 1932, Roy was sentenced to
twelve years in
prison for having conspired to deprive the King Emperor of his
sovereignty in
India in the 1920s. The time he served was reduced; he was released in
late
1936. He was a vocal critic and opponent of Italian and German
fascism. Roy
founded the League of Radical Congressmen in 1938, the Radical
Democratic Party
in 1940, and the Radical Humanist Movement in 1948. The Radical
Humanist
Movement in 1952, together with other humanist movements, founded the
International Humanist and Ethical Union that is today known as
Humanists
International.
Whereas Roy during his communist
phase
argued for “[r]evolutionary nationalism” (1922,
177),
which he distinguished from “reactionary nationalism” (1922,
166,
216; see the same phrases in Roy 1923, 42,
44),
during his humanist phase he opposed “capitalist as well as socialist
Nationalism” (Roy 1960/1947, 102) and argued
that any
nationalism is “a totalitarian cult” (1960/1947,
84)
that needs to be replaced by the universal “brotherhood of free
individuals” (1960/1947, 102) and the
“cosmopolitan commonwealth of
free men and women” that is “ not compatible with the continuation of
National
States” (Roy 1953, 35).
Although some attention has been
given to
Roy’s work in India, his philosophy and theory is widely forgotten.
Roy’s magnum
opus Reason, Romanticism and
Revolution,
which has a great deal in common with Horkheimer and Adorno’s Dialectic
of Enlightenment, is a
forgotten and undiscovered work. In September 2019, Roy’s main book
that was
published in two volumes in 1952 (volume 1) and 1955 (volume 2) had
just 23
citations on Google Scholar[1].
One of the purposes of this article is therefore to point critical
scholars in
the social sciences, humanities, communication and cultural studies
towards
Roy’s works by introducing some of its important aspects.
In
order to
answer the research question that this article poses, it discusses
four aspects
of Roy’s works and assesses their relevance for a critical theory of
communication and culture. These themes are humanism (Section 2),
technology (Section
3), culture and communication (Section 4), and ideology (Section 5).
Section 6
draws some conclusions.
Roy
was
both a humanist and a Marxist. He understood humanism as a romantic
movement (Section 2.1) and engaged with Marx’s works in the context of
humanism
(Section 2.2).
Roy was a radical humanist and humanist Marxist. Humanism stresses the importance of the capacity of humans to change society. It is based on the insight that “man is the maker of his world” (Roy 1953, 47) and the assumption that the human being is “the archetype of society” (Roy 1960/1947, 94). Marx
was a passionate Humanist; and, with a burning faith in revolution, he was also a romanticist. The idea of revolution is a romantic idea, because it presupposes man’s power to remake the world in which he lives. If purposeful human effort is left out of account, social development becomes a mechanistic evolutionary process, making no room for sudden great changes and occasionally accelerated tempo. As the prophet of revolution, Marx was a romanticist. He proclaimed his faith in the creativeness of man which, accelerating the process of social evolution, brought about revolutions. Marx being a Humanist, the force of his theory of revolution was its powerful moral appeal (Roy 1953, 17).
For Roy, humanism is built on the insight that the human being “is essentially rational and therefore moral. Morality emanates from the rational desire for harmonious and mutually beneficial social relations” (Roy 1953, 33). Radical humanism “thinks in terms neither of nation nor of class” (1953, 34), but in terms of the human being. Roy foregrounds the role of human activity in society: history “is the record of man’s struggle for freedom” (1989, 4). For Roy, romanticism means the “passionate belief in the creativeness and freedom of man. […] The idea of revolution, therefore, is a romantic idea. […] The difference between reason and romanticism is that one perceives what is necessary and therefore possible, whereas the other declares impetuously what is desirable, what should be done” (1989, 11).
In society, the human being “is the measure of everything”, which implies that “the merit of any pattern of social organisation or political institution is to be judged by the actual measure of freedom it gives to the individual” (Roy 1953, 38). Comparable to Marx, Roy argues that co-operation is the essence of society (Roy 1953, 38). Marx adds that co-operation is a social production process and a work process, which is why the economy is of particular importance in society (see Fuchs 2020a). Roy (1953) says that the experience of conflict results in the alienation of humans from co-operation and a loss of faith of humans in themselves (91) that means a “crisis of the soul of man” so that “man has forgotten what he is” (91).
A free humanist society requires the realisation of the co-operative essence of society: “Freedom is the progressive elimination of all the factors – physical, social, psychological which obstruct the unfolding of man’s rational, moral and creative potentialities. The function of social relationships should be to secure for individuals, as individuals, the maximum measure of freedom” (Roy 1953, 38). For Roy, freedom
is the supreme value of life, because the urge for freedom is the essence of human existence. […] [The human being’s] urge for freedom […] is undying, eternal. He may not be always conscious of it; often he is not. Nevertheless, it is the basic incentive for him to acquire knowledge and conquer environments by knowing them (Roy 1989, 496-497).
In his main philosophical work Reason, Romanticism and Revolution, published in two volumes in 1952 and 1955, Roy (1989) describes the history of how humanism, rationality, science, philosophy, art, education, and technology have since the time of the Renaissance challenged religious and supernatural authority and the struggles and contradictions involved in this development. Roy argues that modern science and philosophy were not created by the bourgeoisie, but that later the bourgeoisie “patronised them because they served their purpose” (1989, 46). He stresses that Arab philosophy was important for rescuing reason and the thought of ancient Greece while Europe was stuck in the Middle Ages (1989, 41). Arab thought “ultimately reached Europe to stimulate the age-long struggle for spiritual freedom and search for truth” so that the “examination of social political freedom – modern civilisation – resulted from that struggle” (1989, 74). Roy (1989, 42, 68-69, 74, 128, 314) especially foregrounds the importance of Averroes (1126-1198) and Avicenna (980-1037), who built on Aristotle to establish a rationalist and materialist philosophy.
Roy’s stress on Averroes and Avicenna is comparable to the work of Ernst Bloch (2019), who in his book Avicenna and the Aristotelean Left stresses the importance of Avicenna and Averroes who “embraced transformation“ (67) and advanced a “speculative materialism” (67). Whereas the Right Aristotelians believe in supernatural powers that kept humans from struggling for liberation, Left Aristotelians struggle for humanism.
Humanism is internationalist and cosmopolitan; it wants to organise society as a “cosmopolitan commonwealth of free men and women” combined with “a spiritual community, not limited by the boundaries of National States – capitalist, fascist, communist or of any other kind – which will gradually disappear under the impact of cosmopolitan Humanism” (Roy 1953, 35).
A radical
humanist
society includes cultural democracy: “Its culture will be based on
universal
dissemination of knowledge and incentive to scientific and all other
kinds of
creative activity” (Roy 1953, 46). Roy argues that
side by side with the efforts to change economic conditions, efforts should be made to create a cultural atmosphere in which the value of freedom will be appreciated by a larger and larger number of people, an atmosphere in which it will be possible to make more and more people feel the urge for freedom, feel that they are human beings and as such capable of experiencing freedom, here and now (1950a, 188-189).
Freedom requires “economic betterment and [democratic] political
institutions” (1950a, 191) as well as a
culture of
“freedom of thought and judgment” and the advancement of “the spirit
of enquiry
and the ability to distinguish between right and wrong” (190).
Roy opposes both economic and political forms of dictatorship. He argues for economic, political and cultural democracy: “According to Marx, under Socialism, human reason will overcome irrational forces which now tyrannise the life of man” (1953, 18). Roy argues for a radical humanist society that is a grassroots democracy based on people’s committees in politics and co-operatives in the economy. In such a society, local democracy is strengthened (1953, 43). Such committees are also “the school for the political and civic education of the citizen” (1953, 36). For Roy (1989, 474), humanist democracy is “a network of local political schools”: “Every citizen will be informed and consulted for his opinion about the affairs of the state, that is, the political administration of his society” (Roy 1949, 939).
The humanist economy produces for human needs (Roy 1953, 46). It consists of
a network of consumers’ and producers’ co-operatives, and the economic activities of the society shall be conducted and co-ordinated by the people through these institutions. The co-operative economy shall take full advantage of modern science and technology and effect equitable distribution of social surplus through universal social utility services (Roy 1953, 69).
A
radical
humanist democracy is based on “People’s Committees as the primary
constituents
of the democratic State, and co-operatives as the primary units of the
co-operative Commonwealth” (1953, 70):
“Economic
democracy is no more possible in the absence of political democracy than
the
latter is in the absence of the former” (1989, 472).
Roy (1989, 355-358) argues that Kant’s (1724-1804) idealism is based on a dualism of ideas and the thing-in-itself, subject and object, noumenon and phenomena, appearance and reality, science and philosophy, and nature and mind; and that it therefore developed a dogmatic ethics that together with the approaches of Herder (1744-1803), Fichte (1762-1814), and Lessing (1729-1781) advanced German nationalism. Roy (1989, Chapter XVIII) writes that Hegel’s (1770-1831) dialectical philosophy overcame Kant’s dualism, stressing the creativity of the human mind and therefore humanism.
Roy points out that Marx has an “outstanding place in the history of philosophy” because his “materialist monism” questions the dualism of mind and matter by seeing matter “as the ultimate reality capable of producing life” (1989, 417). Roy again and again discusses the relationship of Marx and humanism.
Roy
(1989) argues that Marx’s “view of history and
social
evolution was essentially teleologically fatalistic” (390).
This
view is disproved by Marx’s famous formulation from The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte that humans
“make
their own history, but they do not make it as they please; they do not
make it
under circumstances chosen by themselves, but under circumstances
directly
encountered, given and transmitted from the past“ (1852,
103). History is conditioned by society’s contradictions so that
social
struggles and human practices are the sources of a freedom that goes
beyond and
liberates humans from necessity. History is based on a dialectic of
structuration and collective agency/struggles.
Roy contradicts his own claim that Marx was a historical fatalist when appreciating Marx’s stress on agency and revolution: “The romantic view of life […] leads to the liberating doctrine that man is the maker of the world, developed during a whole period of history from Vico to Marx. […] Marxism is an attempted synthesis between the two apparently antithetical views of life – the rationalist and the romantic” (1989, 12).
Roy (1989) argues that the dialectic is for Marx a rational, scientific law, “Hegelianism applied to human history” (408), and that he combined rationalist dialectics with a romanticist theory of revolution (409-410; 412) so that history is for Marx a “contradiction between rationalism and the romantic notion of revolution” (411). Because of his “emphasis on human action” (412) and his “burning faith in revolution” (420), “Marx was a Humanist, and as such a romanticist” (411). Marx’s philosophy is a “synthesis of rationalism and romanticism” (413). Roy states that “Marx being a humanist, the force of his theory of revolution was its moral appeal. […] In the last analysis, Capital is a treatise on social ethics – a powerful protest against the servitude of the toiling majority” (420).
Roy argues that Marxism needs to be freed from “the fallacy of economic determinism”, which makes it consistent with “Radical Humanism” (421). In the last instance, Roy greatly appreciates Marx as a humanist and revolutionary theorist. But he misinterprets Hegelian dialectics. Dialectics does not just operate at the level of objective contradictions but also at the level of human practices. There is a dialectic of the subjective dialectic and the objective dialectic. And for Marx, class struggle is the subjective dimension of history because the exploited class thereby questions the class relation, by which it is compelled to produce surplus-value that it does not own, and class society. Class struggle as the making and unmaking of class relations between the exploited and the exploited is the subjective dimension of history.
Marx’s quote from the Eighteenth Brumaire does not have, as Roy assumes, a romantic-revolutionary side (humans make their own history) and a dialectical side (they do so under the dialectical contradictions of class society). It does not combine a non-dialectical and a dialectical aspect of society but expresses society’s meta-dialectic of the objective dialectic and the subjective dialectic. Both dimensions of history are dialectical. We cannot say therefore, as Roy (1989, 491) does, that the “fiery prophet of social justice in Marx was more a Humanist than a Hegelian”. Rather, Marx’s dialectic is humanist and his humanism dialectical. The problem of economic determinism and breakdown theory is not immanent in Marx’s application and development of Hegelian dialectics but was the result of, on the one hand, the Bernstein-tradition of social democratic revision of Marx’s theory and, on the other hand, the Stalinist tradition of the vulgarisation of Marx.
Roy
says
that Marx’s insight in the sixth
Feuerbach
thesis that the individual and the human being’s essence are “the
ensemble of the social relations” (Marx 1845, 7)
was “a
great advance in the struggle for freedom” (Roy
1989, 392).
Roy claims that Marx ignores that the activities of individuals
constitute
society (1989, 392). He says Marx omits
“mental
activity” and “conceptual thought” in society and social evolution (393) and “the human nature which underlies the
ensemble
of social relations” (395). He writes that by
neglecting human nature Marx does not recognise “permanent values”
that enable
ethics (396). Roy (1989,
Chapter
IX) here limits his discussion to the German
Ideology and ignores other works of Marx. In Capital, Marx stresses how conceptual thought, mental activities
and human will guide human work:
what
distinguishes the
worst architect from the best of bees is that the architect builds the
cell in
his mind before he constructs it in wax. At the end of every labour
process, a
result emerges which had already been conceived by the worker at the
beginning,
hence already existed ideally. Man not only effects a change of form
in the
materials of nature; he also realizes [verwirklicht] his own
purpose in
those materials. And this is a purpose he is conscious of, it
determines the
mode of his activity with the rigidity of a law, and he must
subordinate his
will to it (Marx 1867, 284).
Roy did not focus on Marx’s Economic
and Philosophic Manuscripts
where Marx identifies a dialectic of the individual and social
structures as
the foundation of society:
just as society itself produces man as man, so is society produced by him […] Social activity and social enjoyment exist by no means only in the form of some directly communal activity and directly communal enjoyment […] that which I make of myself, I make of myself for society and with the consciousness of myself as a social being. […] Above all we must avoid postulating “society” again as an abstraction vis-à-vis the individual. The individual is the social being. […] Man's individual and species-life are not different, however much – and this is inevitable – the mode of existence of the individual is a more particular or more general mode of the life of the species, or the life of the species is a more particular or more general individual life (Marx 1844, 298-299, emphasis in original).
In the German Ideology, the Marxian work Roy (1989, Chapter XIX) is referencing in his discussion, Marx says that the starting point of the analysis of society is “the existence of living human individuals” (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 31). It is not true that Marx does not assume there is no human nature. His whole concept of alienation is based on the notion of human essence. In the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, Marx (1844) points out that the human being is in essence a natural, social, objective-subjective, conscious, self-conscious, sensual, thinking, active, creative, language-using, working being. He also bases a critical humanist ethics on this notion of human essence that advances the insight that class society alienates humans, cripples human nature, and is therefore incompletely human and incompletely social. As a consequence, communism is “practical humanism” and “humanism mediated with itself through the supersession of private property” (Marx 1844, 341).
Written in 1844, the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts were first published in the original German in 1932. Martin Milligan created the first English translation, published in 1959. Roy died in 1954 and was not fluent in German, which means that he could not read the Manuscripts. If he had, his judgement of Marx might have been somewhat different. His criticism of Marx can also be read as a self-criticism of his own earlier phase where he relied much more on determinism and economism than in his later stage. Above all, Roy’s critique should not be seen as relating to Marx, but to the Stalinists that he opposed by the humanist stress on human agency and democratic socialism.
Since the start of a new world economic crisis in 2008, we have experienced not just a brief spring of progressive movements but also the rise and spread of new nationalisms, new authoritarianisms, and new fascism (Fuchs 2018; 2020b). Once again, “[b]ourgeois society stands at the crossroads, either transition to socialism or regression into barbarism” (Luxemburg 1916, 388). Engaging and updating the works of humanist socialists such as Roy, Ernst Bloch, Raya Dunayevskaya, Erich Fromm, Lucien Goldmann, C.L.R. James, Henri Lefebvre, Rosa Luxemburg, Herbert Marcuse, Karl Marx, E. P. Thompson, Raymond Williams, and so on, reminds us that democratic socialism is the strongest weapon against fascism, nationalism, and war.
Humanism shaped how Roy saw various aspects of society, such as technology. The next section discusses his view of the relationship between technology and society.
Roy was a critic of technology as a means of exploitation and domination, but favoured an alternative, non-capitalist modernity that involves a humanist use of technology. Roy differed in this respect from Gandhi (Section 3.1). He provides a dialectical analysis of technology (Section 3.2).
We have already mentioned in the introduction of this article that there was no love lost between Roy and Gandhi. Roy questions the identity of anti-imperialism and nationalism (Roy 1942, 3). He says that the disappearance of British imperialism is a precondition for freedom in India, but that this disappearance will not “necessarily mean freedom for India” (1942, 3). He sees nationalism as an unnecessary and dangerous feature of certain anti-imperialist movements, and as having fascist potentials. In the context of India and the Second World War, Roy was particularly critical of “the fact […] that the sympathies of the average Indian nationalist are all on the side of the Fascist Powers” (1942, 14). Roy believed that the support of the Nazi-fascists by Indians who hated British imperialism would not result in the end of imperialism but in the rise of fascism in India. He opposed any form of nationalism and argued that with the advent of Gandhi’s influence, “authoritarianism became the fundamental principle of Indian Nationalism”, because Gandhi “demanded submission to a spiritual authority” (Roy 2006/1945, 12): “Gandhism is the accepted ideology of Indian Nationalism” (2006/1945, 26).
Roy argues that Indian nationalists “reject precisely what is ‘good’ in
capitalist civilisation”, namely “the tremendous advance of science,
in theory
and practice” (1950b, 109). Gandhism’s focus
on
“non-violence, poverty, continence” (1960/1947,
19),
and “[p]uritanism” (1960/1947, 20) inspires
“the
capitalist and his employees to work hard and spend little, thus
making
possible the accumulation of capital”, which is why “the Mahatma’s
teaching has
acquired great prestige among the capitalists of India” (1960/1947,
20).
Gandhi had a particular view of what role technologies should play in
society. He was critical of industrialisation and modern technologies
because
he saw them as disruptors of traditional life. Gandhi says in this
context:
I don't believe that industrialization is necessary in
any case for any country. It is much less so for India, Indeed I
believe that
independent India can only discharge her duty towards a groaning world
by
adopting a simple but ennobled life by developing her thousands of
cottages and
living at peace with the world. High thinking is inconsistent with a
complicated material life, based on high speed imposed on us by Mammon
worship.
All the graces of life are possible, only when we learn the art of
living nobly
(Gandhi, in Tendulkar 1953, 224-225).
Gandhi
sees
machinery as the cause of imperialism, or what he terms the
exploitation of one
nation by another:
What is the cause of the present chaos? It is
exploitation, I will not say, of the weaker nations by the stronger,
but of
sister nations by sister nations. And my fundamental objection to
machinery
rests on the fact that it is machinery that has enabled these nations
to
exploit others (Gandhi, in Bose 1948, 64-65).
These quotes show that Gandhi equates and conflates modern technology
and
industry on the one side with capitalism and imperialism on the other
side. He
does not see the possibility of an alternative, socialist
modernisation. He
furthermore sees technology as the cause of exploitation. This
position is
different from techno-optimist determinists such as Marshall McLuhan
who see
modern technologies as the enablers and causes of a better future.
Gandhi is a
representative of pessimistic technological determinism that assumes
that
modern technologies with necessity call forth and are the cause of
negative
features of society such as commodification and exploitation. Both
optimistic
and pessimistic technological determinism share the short-sighted
assumption
that it is technology that determines society. They disregard how
society
shapes the character and use of technology and that the relationship
of
technology and society is dialectical and therefore full of
contradictions.
Gandhi favoured the widespread use of
manual technologies, especially the spinning-wheel and the handloom.
He argued
that “[r]estoration
[…] of the
spinning-wheel solves the economic problem of India at a stroke” (1997,
165): “When as a nation we adopt the
spinning-wheel, we not only solve the question of unemployment but we
declare
that we have no intention of exploiting any nation, and we also end
exploitation of the poor by the rich” (1997, 167).
Gandhi
saw the spinning wheel as “the panacea for the growing pauperism of
India” (1983/1948, 441). His view of
technology is
anti-modern and focused on preserving and advancing manual labour and
thereby
toil. Gandhi’s view of manual technologies is, just like his view of
modern
technologies, techno-deterministic. He assumes that the spinning wheel
and the
handloom result in a society without poverty.
Gandhi overlooks that technology is “being looked for and developed with
certain purposes and practices already in mind” (Williams
2003/1974,
7). As Williams states: “Technological determinism is an
untenable notion because it substitutes for real social, political and
economic
intention” (2003/1974, 133). The impacts
of technology
on society are shaped by interests and contradictions in society. In
capitalism, there certainly is an “interlock of military, political
and
commercial intentions” at play in the design and use of science and
technology
(Williams 2003/1974, 137). But there is
also the
potential for shaping science and modern technology by democratic
interests (Williams 2003/1974, 146).
Roy (1950b, 124) does not just criticise that
Gandhi and his followers want an “ethical capitalism”, which means
that they
overlook how capitalist interests shape science and technology and
call forth
negative consequences; he also argues that the “core of Gandhism […]
is its
hostility to industrialism and the modern world” (1960/1947,
18). For Roy, Gandhi’s preaching of the abstention from the use
of
technology and a simple rural life is an ideology that celebrates
poverty and
thereby supports the profit interests of capitalist organisations:
“The
spiritualist doctrine of self-control, simple living, voluntary
poverty, fits
in with the requirements of unsocial capitalism” (1950b,
236).
Roy argues that there is a dialectic of technology and society.
Roy shared concerns about modern technology but rejected technological determinism. He argued that technology should be seen in the context of society and therefore has potentials to advance both slavery and freedom:
the emphasis on freedom at this time is called for by a material factor,
namely, modern technology. There is a very wide-spread fear that this
immense
development of technology will bring slavery for mankind, and the fear
is not
unreasonable. The Nazis were only a little ahead of their time when they
tried
to set up a single world tyranny, and if such a tyranny is ever
established it
will be almost impossible to overthrow. Thus this great development of
technology puts the problem before us in the form of a choice: world
slavery or
world freedom (Roy 1960/1947, 12).
Roy sees modern technology as standing in a dialectical relationship
to
society, which means that technology has certain unpredictable
dynamics, but is
shaped by humans’ interests, which means that in principle humans can
by
practicing overcoming domination and exploitation also shape and
create
technologies that advance freedom, equality and democracy. Roy argued
for the
creation of humanist technologies as part of the struggle for a
humanist society.
“Machine should not be the Frankenstein of modem civilisation.
Created
by men, it must subserve man's purpose – contribute to his freedom” (Roy 1953, 40). He writes that there can be no
freedom
without humanistic modern technology:
Technology is capable, in principle, of providing an enjoyable life for all, and there is no good reason why life should not be enjoyed […] Freedom, equality and democracy are impossible if you reject modern technology (Roy 1960/1947, 21).
Progressive satisfaction of material necessities is the precondition for the individual members of society unfolding their intellectual and other liner human attributes. An economic reorganisation such as will guarantee a progressively rising standard of living will be the foundation of the Radical Democratic State (Roy 1953, 46).
While Gandhi was an anti-modernist, Roy argued for an alternative modernity, a socialist-humanist modernity that shapes, creates and uses technologies in manners that abolish toil and advance freedom, democracy and sustainability:
Science not only enables man to conquer nature,
but also helps
him to understand nature, his relation with it and with other human
beings who
are integral parts of nature. […] Modern technological trends threaten
to offer
mankind at the altar of the Moloch, and create a Frankenstein lusting to
devour
its creator, because the practical, utilitarian value of scientific
knowledge
has been allowed to eclipse its ideal value (Roy
1947a,
iii).
There are strong parallels between Roy’s and Herbert Marcuse’s
analysis of
modern technology. Like Roy, Marcuse rejects anti-technological
ideology that
celebrates toil: “The enemies of technics readily join forces
with a
terroristic technocracy. The philosophy of the simple life, the struggle
against
big cities and their culture frequently serves to teach men distrust of
the
potential instruments that could liberate them” (Marcuse
1998/1941,
63).
Marcuse, just
like Roy,
identifies both emancipatory and repressive potentials of modern
technology and
argues that the actual character and impact of technology depends on
broader
societal contexts, interests and struggles: “Technics by itself can
promote
authoritarianism as well as liberty, scarcity as well as abundance, the
extension as well as the abolition of toil” (Marcuse
1998/1941,
41). Marx and Roy base their analysis on Marx’ Hegelian analysis
of
technology that stresses that there is an antagonism between the essence
of
modern technology and the actual impacts of technology under capitalist
conditions.
Marx, for example, argues that
machinery in itself shortens the hours of labour, but when employed by capital it lengthens them; since in itself it lightens labour, but when employed by capital it heightens its intensity; since in itself it is a victory of man over the forces of nature but in the hands of capital it makes man the slave of those forces; since in itself it increases the wealth of the producers, but in the hands of capital it makes them into paupers (Marx 1867, 568-569).
Marcuse, like Roy, argues for a socialist modernity where technology is shaped and used in manners that overcome toil and advance freedom and technology is governed in a democratic manner:
If everyone has become a potential member of the public bureaucracy […],
society will have passed from the stage of hierarchical
bureaucratization to
the stage of technical self-administration. […] We have pointed to the
possible
democratization of functions which technics may promote and which may
facilitate complete human development in all branches of work and
administration. Moreover, mechanization and standardization may one day
help to
shift the center of gravity from the necessities of material production
to the
arena of free human realization. […] Technological progress would make
it
possible to decrease the time and energy spent in the production of the
necessities of life, and a gradual reduction of scarcity and abolition
of
competitive pursuits could permit the self to develop from its natural
roots.
The less time and energy man has to expend in maintaining his life and
that of
society, the greater the possibility that he can “individualize” the
sphere of
his human realization (Marcuse 1998/1941, 58-59;
63; 64).
In digital capitalism, we
find
both techno-optimism and techno-pessimism. In this context, the
effects of
AI-based automation is a heavily discussed topic.
The futurist Martin Ford (2015)
warns in his book Rise
of
Robots: Technology and the Threat of a Jobless Future that AI-based automation “has a dark side
of its own, and if it results in
widespread unemployment or threatens the economic security of a large fraction of our population” (2015,
283). He writes that
factory
jobs
are disappearing across the globe at a rapid clip. Labor-intensive
manufacturing as a path to prosperity may begin to evaporate for many
developing nations. […] The greatest risk is that we could face a
‘perfect
storm’ – a situation where technological unemployment and
environmental impact
unfold roughly in parallel, reinforcing and perhaps even amplifying
each other”
(Ford 2015, 283; 284).
Accelerationists
such
as Srnicek and Williams (2015) and
Bastani (2019), in contrast to Martin Ford,
point
out that AI-based automation should be entirely welcomed. Srnicek and
Williams
(2015, 179) say that “the
automation of
mundane labour” forms “the basis for a fully postcapitalist economy,
enabling a
shift away from scarcity, work and exploitation, and towards the full
development of humanity”.
Bastani
(2019) argues that new technologies will
result in a
major disruption of society, creating “a world dramatically different
from our
own” (11): “the old world will transition
to the new
more quickly than many imagine” (2019, 77);
and
“within a generation we are set to reach peak human” (2019,
80), ushering in the emergence of fully-automated luxury
communism, “a
society in which work is eliminated, scarcity replaced by abundance
and where
labour and leisure blend into one another” (2019,
50).
Williams and Srnicek (2013) state
that “[w]e want to accelerate
the process of technological
evolution. […] the left must
take
advantage of every technological and scientific advance made possible
by
capitalist society. We declare that quantification is not an evil to
be
eliminated, but a tool to be used in the most effective manner
possible”.
Whereas accelerationists see Artificial
Intelligence
ushering in communism, neoliberals see it as a way of accelerating
corporate
profit-making. The conservative UK government argues in its Industrial
Strategy
that “[e]mbedding AI across the UK will create thousands
of
good quality jobs and drive economic growth” (Department
for
Business, Energy & Industrial Strategy 2019).
While utopian communist
optimism and
neoliberal optimism expect changes from new technologies that they
assess as
positive (communism and capitalist growth respectively), pessimists
argue that
new technologies result in a rise of unemployment, precarity,
inequalities,
social problems, and so on. The basic problem of all of these
approaches is
that they do not see modern technology in modern society as a complex,
contradictory system but rather inscribe certain societal changes into
technology. The actual effects of society depend on the results of
class and
social struggles that shape the character and use of technology in
society.
In the next section, we will
discuss
aspects of Roy’s works that have to do with culture and communication.
Roy developed a distinct form of cultural materialism as part of which he discussed the materialist character of society (Section 4.1) and the relationship of culture and the economy (Section 4.2). He had less to say on communication, but his analysis of culture can inform the critical analysis of communication (Section 4.3).
One basic question for any critical theory is how mind and matter as well as culture and economy are related. In Marxist theory, this question is known as the base/superstructure-problem.
For Roy, the entire world is material. Materialism is “the explanation of the world without the assumption of anything super-natural” (Roy 1940, 227). Matter is “a vibratory substance” (Roy 1947a, 86), “the sole existence” (1947a, 99), “the only reality” and “ontologically real” (1947a, 100). Roy argues that in society, both “ideal and physical” (1989, 8-9) realities are material, have “their respective dynamics or dialectics” and are “mutually influenced” (9). Roy advanced a materialist theory of knowledge. “Man’s relation with nature has been from the very beginning not of passive contemplation, but of action” (Roy 1940, 249). Therefore, “knowledge is action, not passive contemplation” (249); “whatever is within the ken of human consciousness is material. Because, something immaterial (spiritual, in the traditional sense) can never be cognisable to human mind, itself a product of matter in a particular state of organisation” (251).
Roy’s philosophy is monistic and materialist. He stresses that the non-human and the human world are material. For Roy, the human being is entirely material because the body and the mind are physical entities developed in the course of evolution. In the realm of humans and their societies, Roy stresses the dialectical interaction of ideas/physical reality, mind/body, nature/society, environment/individual, and economy/culture. All of these realms are expressions of matter as a dynamic, vibratory process. There are no ideas without the human mind’s embeddedness into and interaction with the body and a natural and social environment.
Roy deals with the question of the means of production in society. He stresses that the brain is humanity’s key means of production:
But may we not ask who created the first means of production? What was
there
originally? Did the first man appear with hammer and sickle in hand? No.
But he
did come into the world with another means of production, the most
powerful ever
created. And that was his brain […] We are all born with it, and it
remains our
basic asset, provided that we can appreciate its worth and make proper
use of
it. If you prefer a crude hammer, or even an electric hammer, or
something
still better, the most modern technological inventions, to your brain, I
wish
you luck (Roy 1960/1947, 65-66).
The
creation of
the first extra-organic means of production was a deed done by
an animal
with highly developed brain, capable of thought. An idea preceded the creation
of the first means of production (Roy 1960/1947, 93).
The brain is a means of production, and produces the most revolutionary commodity (Roy 1953, 36).
Roy (1989, 17) stresses that conceptual thought
is
characteristic of humans. Conceptual thought is “thinking stimulated by
mental
images” (1989, 17). “Conceptual thought depends
on
language. So, it can be said that man is fully differentiated from his
animal
ancestry only when he coins words for expressing definite ideas” (17).
Animals articulate sounds but this activity is
entirely dependent on stimuli from their immediate environment; they
lack
conceptual thought (17). This means that humans
have
the capacity to anticipate and reflect on the consequences of their
actions,
select among different potential actions, make moral judgements that
guide
their actions, and discuss and communicate their feelings, actual and
potential
choices, interests, experiences, morals, and actions. Humans are
rational,
anticipatory, self-conscious, thinking, creative, moral, languaging,
social,
communicative, societal beings. Roy (1989, 479)
argues
that the human being is “a thinking animal”. But humans are also social,
communicative beings.
What needs to be added to Roy’s approach is the crucial role of work and production in human existence (see Fuchs 2020a). Based on their capacities as rational, thinking, creative, social beings, humans engage in the social production of ideas, technologies that they use to transform the world, goods that satisfy human needs, collective decisions, worldviews, and culture. They together produce an economy, a political system, and culture, i.e. forms of sociality and social relations. Work is the process of social production through which humans create something new that satisfies their needs. Social production means that the economy and work are at the heart of all social realms, including the political and cultural life. At the same time, social systems go beyond mere production by having emergent qualities. Once humans produce structures, these structures have specific features and a particular logic that go beyond economic necessity and are shaped by human interests and their contradictions.
The dialectic of culture and the economy is based on social production, which means that the combination of the human capacities to produce and to be social are at the heart of all realms of society, including the economy and culture. Each social realm is based on social production that forms the material foundation of humans and society. Each social realm also has particular, emergent dynamics and contradictions that cannot be reduced to production. The capacity for social production is itself a combination of the capacity to form and communicate ideas and the capacity to experience, engage with and transform the environment, i.e. a dialectic of communication and work. Social production combines the work character of communication and the communicative character of work (Fuchs 2020a).
An important question for any theory of society is that of how culture and the economy are related.
Roy challenges the assumption that culture and ideas are reducible to the economy and therefore derive from economic structures, i.e. productive forces and the relations of production. He stresses that culture has a particular logic that is based on and influences human experiences and events in society:
The logical development of ideas and the generation of new social forces take place simultaneously, together providing the motive force of history. But in no given period can they be causally connected except in the sense that action is always motivated by ideas” (Roy 1989, 10).
We do not accept the Marxist doctrine that moral values, cultural patterns, aesthetic tastes, are all ideological super-structures of economic relations […] the so-called ideological super-structure is not hanging in the air; that it too has its own roots. Ideas, undoubtedly, are influenced by social experience, influencing, at the same time, social and historical events. But they have a logic and dynamics of their own (Roy 1960/1947, 70-71).
Ideation is a physiological process resulting from the awareness of environments. But once they are formed, ideas exist by themselves, governed by their own laws. […] Cultural patterns and ethical values are not mere ideological super-structures of established economic relations. They are also historically determined – by the logic of the history of ideas (1953, 52).
For Roy, ideologies and ideas are “structures standing by themselves” and not superstructures (1960/1947, 71). Materialism means for Roy that the productive forces do not determine history because they are “the collective expression of the creativeness of man, and the creative man is always a thinking man” (1989, 8). This means that humans, because of their self-consciousness and “the creative role of intelligence” (1989, 8), have the capacity to make choices, to envision the future, to identify and act based on interests, and to organise and act collectively.
In his book Revolution and Counter-Revolution in China, Roy (1946/1930, 3; 6-7), following Plekhanov, argues that “social evolution” is determined by “the natural conditions and forces of production” (1946/1930, 3). Roy therefore argues, for example, that in ancient China, the “evolution of private property […] was caused by the development of the means of production”, and that the “progressive perfection of tools in the hands of man – the development of the means of production – again is determined by physical conditions” (1946/1930, 17). The problem with this view is that technology, nature and work as aspects of the forces of production do not operate independently but within definite social relations between human beings. The views of Roy and Plekhanov disregard the relations of production and are therefore prone to a naturalistic and technological determinism. Roy’s critique of economic determinism during his last, humanist phase of intellectual development was partly also self-criticism of his earlier thought.
Humanism is both a worldview and a political movement. Any movement has a worldview that guides and interacts with its practices. There is a dialectic of ideas and practices. The rise of various humanist movements is not reducible to the economic structure of feudalism but stands in the context of class and social struggles and therefore collective social practices. Humans who oppose a certain social order and organise themselves engage in collective practices and develop collective ideas that guide their collective struggle. Marx’s father was a relatively well-situated lawyer. Engels’ father owned large textile factories in Salford (UK) and Barmen (Prussia). Rosa Luxemburg’s father was a timber trader. George Lukács’ mother was the heir of a rich timber trading family and his father was a bank director. These examples show that the class and family backgrounds of those who engage in certain movements do not mechanically determine their political positions and the question of whether they join certain movements. That there is a relative autonomy of ideas so that ideas are socially produced and interact with economy and society means that political position and worldview cannot be read from and are not determined by class background.
Marx points out that once a certain ideology becomes historically attached to a class, this class supports and creates individuals and groups who develop this ideology. He speaks of a “division of mental and material labour” (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 60) in the ruling class: “inside this class one part appears as the thinkers of the class (its active, conceptive ideologists, who make the formation of the illusions of the class about itself their chief source of livelihood)” (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 60). The
individuals composing the ruling class possess among other things consciousness, and therefore think. Insofar, therefore, as they rule as a class and determine the extent and compass of an historical epoch, it is self-evident that they do this in its whole range, hence among other things rule also as thinkers, as producers of ideas, and regulate the production and distribution of the ideas of their age: thus their ideas are the ruling ideas of the epoch (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 59).
Given a division of labour in the ruling class, one cannot assume that capitalists directly determine the ideas disseminated with the help of books, public debates, business schools, the media, and so on. Intellectuals have their own logic and interests and in the first instance often strive to accumulate reputation and not monetary capital. With the help of funding, donations, consultancy, cultural networks, the support of think tanks, the ownership of media, etc., capital exerts indirect pressure on the realm of the production of ideology. At the same time, ideologues who strive for reputation are also keen on shaping the ideas of members of the ruling class and the political elite in order to increase their own reputation. Similar things can be said about the relationship of intellectuals and politicians who strive to accumulate power.
There is a complex relationship between ideologues, political actors and economic actors in capitalist society. They strive towards accumulating reputation (ideologues), power (political actors) and money capital (capitalists). Insofar as these logics coincide, they enter mutually beneficial relations that can develop their own contradictions and can therefore also break down.
In some, but certainly not all passages of his writings that focus on culture, it seems that Roy sees culture as almost independent from political economy, simply saying that his approach is materialist because everything including ideas is material. The consequence of such an assumption is a materialist dualism where the whole world is material, while within society there are independent material substances, namely culture and the economy. Culture cannot be reduced to political economy; however, it is also not fully independent but grounded in the economy, and at the same time relatively autonomous.
Roy (1947b, 898) argues that Marx’s suggestion that being determines consciousness implies that “man’s ideals are shaped by the tools with which he works”. However, a mode of production does not only consist of the productive forces but also interacts with the relations of production. Marx suggests that consciousness is embedded into society’s social relations because humans are ensembles of social relations, which means that technology is not, as assumed by technological determinism, the determining factor of society. Rather, social relations are the determining factor of culture, ideas, politics, and the economy, which means that society only exists in and through humans’ social relations.
Marx argues that the mode of production is not simply the “physical existence of the individuals”, but “a definite form of activity of these individuals” in which they express their lives (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 31). It is “a definite mode of life” (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 31): “The production of ideas, of conceptions, of consciousness, is at first directly interwoven with the material activity and the material intercourse of men – the language of real life” (36). Material production includes “[c]onceiving], thinking, the mental intercourse of men” (36), “mental production as expressed in the language of […] politics, laws, morality, religion, metaphysics, etc.” (36). This means that for Marx ideas are material entities and thinking is a material process. And the production of ideas is a social process. Culture as the production and circulation of ideas and meanings takes place within the ensemble of social relations that constitutes the human subject. Marx and Engels stress that ideas depend on the social relations of the humans who think, create, share, and reproduce them:
Ideas can never lead beyond an old world order but only beyond the ideas of the old world order. Ideas cannot carry out anything at all. In order to carry out ideas men are needed who can exert practical force (Marx and Engels 1845, 119).
Undeterred by this examination, the French Revolution gave rise to ideas which led beyond the ideas of the entire old world order (Marx and Engels 1845, 119).
In respect to Marx’s (1845-1846) passages from the German Ideology mentioned in the preceding paragraph, Roy (1989, 393-394) argues that Marx does not see that consciousness is foundational for human activities. This assessment is flawed: Marx conceives of consciousness as material because the brain is a material system. And self-consciousness enables human freedom:
free, conscious activity is man's
species-character. […]
Conscious life activity distinguishes man immediately from animal life
activity. It is just because of this that he is a species-being. Or it
is only
because he is a species-being that he is a conscious being, i.e., that
his own
life is an object for him. Only because of that is his activity free
activity.
Estranged labour reverses this relationship, so that it is just because
man is
a conscious being that he makes his life activity, his essential
being, a
mere means to his existence (Marx 1844, 276).
The struggle against religious and monarchic authority has expressed
itself not
just in the realm of politics and the economy but also in realms such as
philosophy, science, art, education, and literature, i.e. in cultural
forms.
The political-economic and the cultural movements and social forms that
challenged the feudal social order that dominated the Dark Ages all
shared
certain goals and interests but did not originate from the same people
and were
not organised within one overall unified, consistent movement. The
Enlightenment was a political-economic and cultural movement consisting
of many
strands that challenged the feudal system’s economic, political, and
cultural
structures.
As one example for the relationship of ideas and the economy, Roy discusses the relationship of humanism and the bourgeoisie: “Renaissance Humanism was not the ideology of the rising bourgeoisie” (1989, 79). Humanism rather started and developed as a movement that challenged religious, monarchic, aristocratic, feudal authority and rule. It took on different forms, including liberalism, reactionary romanticism, socialism, and communism, which means that humanism is a contradictory movement.
Liberalism developed in the sixteenth century independently from the economy “according to the logic of the evolution of thought” (1989, 300). Later on, “a particular class” – the bourgeoisie – “accepted it” (300). Roy argues that given this sequence, liberalism is not “the ideology of the bourgeoisie” and the “philosophy of capitalism” (300, see also 303; 318). He writes that liberalism and capitalism developed simultaneously and concomitantly (302) and sees liberalism as going beyond economic philosophy and extending into politics and the ways of life (301-302). For Roy, the origin of liberalism is “the movement for the secularisation of politics” (303). He argues that liberalism did not originate as a capitalist project but was at a certain point of time adopted and shaped by the bourgeois class.
The classical liberal thinkers John Locke (1632-1704) and Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) predominantly focused on political philosophy. Thinkers such as Adam Smith (1723-1790), Thomas Malthus (1766-1834), David Ricardo (1772-1823), James Mill (1773-1836), and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) extended classical liberalism from politics to political economy. As a consequence, classical political economy developed. These thinkers combined economic and moral philosophy. In contrast to Locke and Hobbes, they lived at the time of the decay of feudalism, the emergence of industrial capitalism, the Enlightenment, and the French Revolution. It is certainly true, as Roy argues, that liberalism did not originate as the ideology of capitalism, but as a broader ideology and philosophy that in the 18th and 19th centuries was turned into the ideology of capitalism. This was not an accident but had to do with the search of the rising bourgeoisie for an ideology guiding its practices and justifying its interests.
A certain mode of production or phase of development of the economy does not result in a single dominant idea system or form of culture. Ideas and culture cannot be read off the mode of production. We can learn from Roy that a mode of production influences but does not determine forms of culture. In relation to a particular mode of production, a variety of cultural forms and cultural contradictions exist. In his Introduction to the Grundrisse, Marx (1857) speaks in this context of “the uneven development of material production relative to e.g. artistic development” (109, emphasis in original) and stresses that in “the case of the arts, it is well known that certain periods of their flowering are out of all proportion to the general development of society, hence also to the material foundation, the skeletal structure as it were, of its organization”. This means that culture can but does not necessarily have to flourish in periods of political-economic crises. A crisis of political economy can but does not have to be accompanied by the demise of dominant cultural forms and the emergence of radical cultural novelties.
Communication is an important theme of cultural theory that the next sub-section addresses.
For Roy (1950a), culture has to do with the ways we experience the world and with the intellectual and emotional world. Communication is a key feature of culture. Wherever there is communication there is culture, and wherever we communicate we produce and reproduce culture. Marx argues that “neither thoughts nor language in themselves form a realm of their own, that they are only manifestations of actual life” (Marx and Engels 1845-1846, 447). And actual life is the “ensemble of the social relations” of individuals, groups, social systems and society (Marx 1845, 7). Culture and communication exist as social relations in which humans produce meaning in the world. These cultural relations exist in connection to society’s ensemble of social relations and the ensemble of social relations that humans engage in.
Roy (1940) argues that “[s]ense-perceptions, human experience, gained not in passive contemplation (it cannot be done that way), but in active functioning of the human organism, and having for their source the material world existing objectively outside our consciousness, independent of it, is the point of departure of all knowledge” (1940, 252). He writes that
knowledge is derived not in passive contemplation, but in action. ‘Philosophers have interpreted the world in various ways, but the real task is to transform it’. Only in the process of transforming the world continuously, does the store of human knowledge endlessly increase; and the knowledge of a given epoch is valuable in so far as it enables man to transform the world, thereby opening a new epoch of progress (1940, 268).
Roy states that “[k]nowledge is possible because there is a causal connection between mind and matter” (1947a, 195). Ideas “represent the knowledge of things” (195); they result from mental activities (196); “[k]nowledge results from perception, which is organic reaction to physical contacts” (195). We must add that knowledge is not only formed by humans engaging with physical environments but also with social environments. Humans interact with things when they touch, feel, move, and change them, but things do not talk; they have no language. In the social and societal environment, humans act as languaging, communicating beings so that they interact symbolically with each other, which means that they interpret each other and form meanings of each other.
Living beings react to the world they are part of and that they experience, which is why humans establish a relationship between mind and the world (198). Knowledge is at the same time objective and subjective (198): knowledge is the subjective, mental act of cognising the world (202) that constructs knowledge as an object in the human mind (203). Perception is the process that puts the human subject in relation to the world. Knowing/cognition builds on perception. It is “not a tacit reception or recoding of messages from the external world” (204-205), but an “intelligent reaction” to “messages” that “are stimuli” and sense data (205) gained through experience: “Cognition is an interpretative, denotative, selective, act” (205); “[k]nowledge is a conceptual scheme born out of the insight into the nature of things, gained through critical examination, rational co-ordination and logical deduction of perceptual data” (206).
Roy does not discuss communication in detail, but we can build on his insights. We can apply Roy’s ideas to the communication process: in communication, humans establish relations between their minds and thereby between individuals that constitute, produce, and reproduce the social world. They produce and reproduce social relations (Fuchs 2020a). When human beings A and B communicate, then A constructs B as an object in A’s mind and B constructs A as an object in B’s mind. They sense, perceive, cognise, and experience each other, and react to each other’s messages by making meaning of them and creating and externalising symbols as a response. For communicating, humans use their brains as major intellectual means of production, and linguistic and symbolic means of communication through words, grammar, bodily movements, etc. Words are “vehicles for the expression and communication of […] emotions and ideas” (Roy 1989, 7); “[l]anguages develop to serve the purpose of coordinating disjointed ideas and emotions” (Roy 1989, 7).
Communication is the process through which humans make meaning out of each other. In communication, they mutually reveal ideas, i.e. interpret the world, to each other. Communication is the production of social relations where at least two humans externalise knowledge in symbolic forms, and cognise each other and each other’s ideas, such that they interpret the other and their ideas. In communication, humans create messages that reach other humans, beginning a perception and cognition process that results in the construction of a mutual knowledge of each other. Communication is the mutual externalisation of knowledge through the human sense organs, and the internalisation of externalised knowledge. Given that, for Roy, cognition is an active process, communication that is based on cognition is also an active production process: communication is the human production and reproduction of social relations (Fuchs 2020a).
The realm of culture, i.e. the production and communication of ideas and meanings, is an important aspect of Roy’s theory of society. Roy also gives particular attention to the critique of repressive ideas, namely the ideologies of nationalism and fascism. The next section discusses his analysis of ideology.
“An ideology is a system of ideas; in other words,
an ideology is the ideal sanction for social and political practices”
(Roy 1960/1947, 67). Roy has a general
understanding of
ideology and differs in this respect from thinkers such as Georg
Lukács (1971, 66), who sees ideology as
reified consciousness
that legitimates the interest of the ruling class by trying to “deceive the other classes and to ensure that their class consciousness
remains amorphous”, or Theodor W. Adorno, who understands ideology as “a consciousness which is objectively necessary and yet at the same time
false, as the intertwining of truth and falsehood” (Adorno
1954,
189).
Such critical concepts of ideology stress the illusionary and
manufactured character of ideas that make up an ideology and their
legitimating
role in class structure. Roy speaks of an “ideal sanction for social
and
political practices”, which can in one sense be understood as the
legitimation
of class relations but is on the other hand formulated in a very
general
manner, such that, seemingly, for Roy ideology exists in all society
and not
just, as for Lukács, in class societies.
Leaving aside problems of definitions, Roy in his works analyses the
ideological structure of some of the main ideologies of the capitalist
age,
namely liberalism (Section 5.1), nationalism and fascism (Section
5.2), which
resonates with the Frankfurt School’s analyses (Section 5.3)
The Enlightenment was a movement
against the
power of the church, the monarch, and the aristocracy. In the 19th
century,
liberalism started taking on the form of utilitarianism. Thinkers such
as David
Hume (1711-1776), Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), James Mill (1773-1836)
and John
Stuart Mill (1806-1873) influenced utilitarian thought. Roy states
that
the liberal doctrine of laisser faire served the purpose of rising Capitalism; and the rule of law came to be the rule of a minority which under the given circumstances had the power to make laws. Liberalism appeared to provide a moral justification of the economic exploitation of man by man and a philosophical sanction for the modern political theories which subordinated the individual to the State (Roy 1989, 330).
Liberal practice has in capitalism
undermined the principle of freedom and liberties for all.
Utilitarianism’s principle of maximising individual utility and
happiness as much as possible and doing so for the greatest number of
individuals is for Roy based on a “clash of two categorial
imperatives” (Roy 1989, 340): individualistic
and collectivistic. The
one side of this antagonism bears a potential for the advancement of
economic
individualism in the form of laissez
faire-style capitalism that postulates profit maximisation with
no
government intervention in the economy (342).
The
other side of the antagonism fetishises collectivism (the happiness of
the
largest number of people) at the expense of universal rights of all
individuals. “The orthodox utilitarian dictum logically justifies
suppression
of a minority even of forty-nine (because fifty-one is a greater
number)” (347). It therefore has the
potential to provide “a moral
sanction for the various totalitarian cults” (340),
to
undermine “the equality of men”, to advance the “negation of
Democracy”, and to
herald “the advent of dictatorship” (345).
An example of utilitarian logic can be found in debates on the British
referendum to leave the European Union. Prime Minister Boris Johnson
has
repeatedly used utilitarian arguments for justifying the need for a
“hard
Brexit” without an agreement between the EU and the UK. Johnson
identifies “the
people” as those who support Brexit. Here are two examples of this
demagogic
logic of reducing “the people” to those who support Brexit:
Boris Johnson: “What I think people want us to do is to leave the
European
Union on October 31st” (BBC 2019).
Boris
Johnson: “But
the way to unite the country, I am afraid, is to get this thing done.
[…] What
people want to see is a resolution and they want to see us get this
thing done.
And that’s what we’re gonna do” (Johnson 2019).
In Britain’s 2016 EU referendum,
51.9
percent of the voters opted for Brexit and 48.1 percent against it.
This means
there is a very large minority that Johnson excludes from his notion
of the
people. He speaks in favour of the majority and argues for the
interest of the
largest group of voters while disregarding the interests of the
minority. The
result is that he advances the political polarisation of the country
into two
hostile camps.
The basic problem of utilitarianism is that its ethical foundations deny
“the permanence of moral values” (Roy 1989, 340).
Utilitarian
ethics is a “relativist morality” and “ethical nihilism” (341).
The result is that utilitarianism has both
potentials for the fetishization of individual interests (capitalism’s
individualism without socialism) and the fetishization of (partial)
social
interests (collectivism without individuality such as in fascism and
Stalinism). It lacks a commitment to universalism (universal rights)
and an
ethical and political dialectic of individual and social rights.
Roy (1989) argues that positivism and
empiricism fetishize scientific knowledge as “a mathematical god” and
is a
“neo-mysticism” (456; see also 457).
Positivism
is one aspect of utilitarian liberalism. The logic of calculability
supports the accumulation of capital and power because it allows the
reduction
of society to the instrumental logic of costs and benefits.
There are parallels of Roy’s critique of positivism to the analysis
advanced by Frankfurt School authors such as Friedrich Pollock,
Theodor W.
Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Jürgen Habermas, and related thinkers such as
Alfred
Sohn-Rethel and Georg Lukács.
The Frankfurt School stresses the instrumental character of positivism.
Pollock and Adorno, two key members of the Frankfurt School, argue
that the
rise of mathematics in the social sciences denotes the “convergence of
social-scientific methods toward those of the natural sciences” and
is “the
child of a society that reifies people” (Pollock
and
Adorno 2011, 20). For Horkheimer (2004/1947,
41), “[p]ositivism is philosophical technocracy”. Habermas (1971, 67) warns that positivism is the
“immunization
of the sciences against philosophy”. Horkheimer
and
Adorno (2002/1947, 25) argue
that the
logic of calculation is the foundation of barbarism: “With
the spread of
the bourgeois commodity economy the dark horizon of myth is
illuminated by the
sun of calculating reason, beneath whose icy rays the seeds of the new
barbarism are germinating”.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel was not a member of the Frankfurt School but was in
contact with Adorno, with whom he shared the critique of positivism. Sohn-Rethel (1978)
argues
that class society’s division of labour includes the separation
between head
and hand. Positivism is the fetishism of mechanistic, quantifying,
mathematical
reasoning. It is an expression and result of the division of labour.
Georg Lukács inspired the Frankfurt School’s analysis of
instrumental reason. Lukács (1971) points
out that
positivism is anti-dialectical: “The methodology
of the natural sciences which forms the methodological ideal of every
fetishistic science and every kind of Revisionism reject the idea of
contradiction and antagonism in its subject matter” (1971,
10). Mathematics does not see “the whole system at once” (117).
The logic of quantification reduces explanations
to basic principles (reductionism) and believes in the exact
predictability and
calculability of the world (determinism) (117).
In the contemporary social sciences and humanities, digital positivism has emerged as a new form of positivism. It propagates quantitative digital methods, namely big data analytics. The social sciences are thereby re-envisioned as computational social science, a paradigm focused on large datasets, quantification, mathematics, and calculation. Such approaches set out to explain the world based on the analysis of big stocks and flows of data. The problem is that the analysis of big data does not tell us everything that matters. It cannot properly study human motivations, feelings, experiences, norms, morals, values, interpretations, concerns, fears, hopes, etc. It lacks a focus on society’s qualities.
Roy (1953, 8) argues that there is a
contradiction between “the philosophy and the political practice of
Liberalism”. Capitalism’s
“cut-throat competition” undermined democracy and resulted in “the
stormy rise
of Fascism” (9). Roy observed how the
failures of
liberalism resulted on the one hand in fascism and on the other hand
in
Stalinism, the fetishization of the collectives of the nation and the
working
class: “A political system and an economic experiment which
subordinate the man
of flesh and blood and to an imaginary collective ego, be it the
nation or a
class, cannot possibly be the suitable means for the attainment of the
goal of
freedom” (1953, 53-54).
Roy describes and analyses a negative
dialectic
of the liberal Enlightenment whereby the alienation caused by
liberalism let liberalism turn against itself and its own political
and moral
values, which called forth terror and violence. According to Roy,
19th-century
liberalism’s utilitarianism, its “law of the jungle” (1989,
428), and its atomising individualism called forth “the superman
cult” (428), cults of collectivism (427),
irrationalism
(428, 445),
“the cult of leadership” (445), and
dictatorship (445). The result was “the
mystic collectivist cult” (436) of fascism
and Stalinism: “In modern Liberalism, the
individual became the economic man. […] But in the context of the
capitalist
society, the economic man could exist either as a slave or as a
slaveowner.
That debasement of the individual discredited the liberal democratic
doctrine
of individual freedom. […] Ultimately, democracy was destroyed in a
fierce
clash of totalitarian dictatorships” (Roy 1989,
464),
namely fascism and Stalinism. Roy says that humans created a machine
that now
enslaves them (477) so that the “struggle for
freedom
[…] ultimately” deprives humans of freedom (477).
The
“creations of man have reduced man to nothingness”, which means the
“complete
subordination of the creator to his creation”. Marx (1844)
termed this process alienation.
The rise of fascism in Europe was one of the consequences of the
Enlightenment’s negative dialectic:
In Europe, Fascism represents a reaction to the negative features of the capitalist civilisation, namely, lonesomeness and helplessness of the individual, resulting from his atomisation. These features are accentuated in the period where the progressive potentialities of capitalist economy are exhausted, and monopolist capitalism increases the degree of social insecurity, particularly for the middle and lower classes. In that period, the reaction becomes more violent, and the cultural sanctions of the capitalist civilisation – humanism, rationalism and liberalism – are assaulted (Roy 2006/1945, 22).
Liberal individualism and atomism
that
expresses itself as the exploitation of wage-workers, the
fetishization of
private property, capital accumulation, cut-throat competition, and
the logic
of the accumulation of capital in the economy and of power in the
state-system has
backfired. The social void it created has been filled with movements
for
repressive collectivism. Whereas liberal individualism fetishizes the
individual at the expense of social freedom, fascism and Stalinism
fetishize
the collectives of the nation and the state at the expense of
individual
freedom. Roy (1989, 477) argues that in
contrast, a
radical humanist democracy has to “reconcile individual freedom with
social
organisation”.
In respect to liberalism’s self-contradiction, we find parallels between
Roy’s work and Horkheimer and Adorno’s (2002/1947)
Dialectic of Enlightenment.
Horkheimer and Adorno (2002/1947, xvi)
argue that capitalism entails the tendency of the “self-destruction of
enlightenment” (2002/1947, xvi),
resulting
in “the reversion of enlightened civilization to barbarism” (xix).
Capitalism’s structures of exploitation
and domination turned against liberalism’s enlightenment values and in
the last
instance resulted in Auschwitz: “After the brief interlude of
liberalism in
which the bourgeois kept one another in check, power is revealing
itself as archaic
terror in a fascistically rationalized form” (68).
Horkheimer (2004/1947, v) points out that
in capitalism, Enlightenment tends to nullify itself and transform
into its
opposite, namely dehumanisation: “Advance
in technical facilities for enlightenment is accompanied by a process
of
dehumanization. Thus progress threatens to nullify the very goal it is
supposed
to realize – the idea of man”. Like Roy, Horkheimer points out that
Enlightenment reason emerged as a protest against religion. But in
capitalism,
reason turned into an instrument of domination and exploitation: “Having given up autonomy, reason
has become
an instrument. […] Reason has become completely harnessed to the
social
process. Its operational value, its role in the domination of men and
nature,
has been made the sole criterion” (14-15).
As a
result, “the advance of enlightenment tends at certain points to
revert to
superstition and paranoia” (21). “Less
and less
is anything done for its own sake. […] In the view of formalized
reason, an activity
is reasonable only if it serves another purpose […] In other words,
the
activity is merely a tool, for it derives its meaning only through its
connection with other ends” (25). The
reduction
of reason to a mere instrument neutralises reason and calls forth
irrationalism:
“At the moment of consummation, reason has become irrational and
stultified” (87). Liberalism turns into
authoritarianism.
“[L]iberalism and authoritarianism tend to interact in a way that
helps to vest
an ever more rigid rational control in the institutions of an
irrational world”
(49). With the rise of fascism in
Europe,
“[r]eason […] ultimately destroyed itself” (Horkheimer
1941,
367). Fascism is an irrational rationality: “The new order of
Fascism
is Reason revealing itself as unreason” (1941,
387).
Horkheimer and Adorno’s argument is
that
when reason becomes instrumental reason it not only undermines
critique but
also calls forth irrational forces that advance terroristic systems
such as
fascism and Stalinism.
“Technological
rationality” is Herbert
Marcuse’s term for what Horkheimer calls “instrumental reason”:
“Rationality is
being transformed from a critical force into one of adjustment and
compliance.
Autonomy of reason loses its meaning in the same measure as the
thoughts, feelings
and actions of men are shaped by the technical requirements of the
apparatus
which they have themselves created” (Marcuse
1998/1941,
49). Marcuse (1988/1965)
argues that technological rationality results
in rational irrationality. “In the unfolding of capitalist
rationality, irrationality becomes
reason” (207);
“bourgeois
reason negates itself in its consummation” (221).
Comparably
to Horkheimer and Marcuse, Roy (1960/1947, 94)
argues that fascism makes “man only an automation, a robot, a small
wheel in a
gigantic social machinery”.
The notions of technological
rationality and
instrumental reason express several dimensions of capitalism and class
society:
·
Technology as an
instrument of
domination:
Technology is, under the conditions of domination and capitalism, the
dominant
groups’ instrument for the exploitation, control, and surveillance of
others.
·
Capitalism as
social technology:
Capitalism is a type of social technology that reduces humans to the
status of
workers and consumers and treats them as the instrument, thing, and
resource
for achieving the goal of capital accumulation. Capitalism is a
machine that
accumulates capital and produces commodities. It alienates humans from
their
humanness.
·
Ideology as the
instrumentalization of
consciousness:
In order to reproduce itself, domination requires ideologies that make
structures of domination appear natural, without alternative, and
good. Such
ideologies are for example consumerism, fascism, nationalism, racism,
technocracy, technological determinism, neoliberalism, conservatism,
militarism, etc. Ideology is a particular form of technological
rationality
that tries to eliminate critical and dialectical thought in order to
instil
blind, uncritical faith in ruling ideas into humans. It involves the
attempt to
reduce human consciousness to the status of machines. Attempts to
reify
consciousness try to manipulate humans.
·
Technological
determinism:
Technological determinism is a specific form of ideology that sees
technology
as being autonomous from society, as the cause of society’s changes,
problems
or advances.
Since
2008, many
societies have experienced profound economic, political and
ideological crises
that together have resulted in a surge
of
new nationalisms and new authoritarianisms (Fuchs
2018;
2020b). Neoliberal capitalism has
experienced a new
negative dialectic of the enlightenment. New nationalisms and
authoritarianisms
are the result of the negative dialectic of neoliberal capitalism
and the new
imperialism. The commodification of everything, entrepreneurialism,
privatisation, deregulation, financialisation, globalisation,
deindustrialisation, outsourcing, precarisation and the new
individualism have
backfired, extended and intensified inequalities and crisis
tendencies, which have
created a fertile ground for new nationalisms, right-wing extremism
and new
fascism.
Roy gives particular attention to the analysis and critique of nationalism and fascism. He argues that fascism is a militant and terroristic form of capitalism. The bourgeoisie is defending its “waning power with the bloody instruments of Fascist dictatorship” (1938, 6); its members throw off “the mask of parliamentarism and wield their dictatorship openly” (38). Roy argues that fascism cannot be reduced to monopoly capitalism because there are forms of monopoly capitalism without a terroristic state. He rather argues that in phases of crisis where fascist movements rise, the capitalist class may find fascist rule a means suited for fostering exploitation and capital accumulation and might therefore support such movements:
Fascism is the most outstanding phenomenon of contemporary history. It has to be explained. It is not enough to call it monopoly capitalism or Hitler Imperialism, whatever that curious phrase might mean. It is not historically correct to identify Fascism with monopoly capitalism. The latter had been in operation in other countries years before Fascism rose in Germany. In those countries, Fascists could not capture power. On the other hand, Italy, where Fascism first succeeded, was an economically backward country. Fascism cannot be explained unless ideological antecedents, the cultural atmosphere, are taken into account. The doctrines with which Fascism swept to power in Germany can be traced in the ideological and cultural history of that country. Fascism also was a result of the dynamics of ideas. Monopoly capitalism, more correctly, capitalism in decay, found that those ideas could serve its purpose very well (Roy 1960/1947, 68).
Roy argues that fascism is
different from imperialism. Fascism is not simply a form of
imperialism.
“Capitalism creates Fascism as the weapon for its last defence, only
when it
can no longer provide the foundation for Imperialism” (Roy
1943,
60). Roy (1989)
points out that the dialectic of the
Enlightenment’s weakening of reason results “in the storm of emotions
running
wild” so that it “is easier to sway the people by appeals to their
emotions and
prejudices than to their reason. […] Therefore, democracy has
everywhere
degenerated into demagogy” (468).
The rise of new authoritarianism has been accompanied by a mass of public
discourses that are driven by emotions and ideology. Authoritarians
often do
not believe in anything that can be reasonably explained and proofed,
believing
only what they want to believe and what fits into their ideology. They
often distrust
intellectuals, experts, and academia.
During the campaigns for the 2016 Brexit referendum, Michael Gove, then
the British Secretary of State for Justice, declared in a television
interview
that citizens should not and do not trust experts: “I
think that people in this country have had enough of
experts […] from organisations with acronyms, saying that they know
what is
best and get it consistently wrong”.[2] Some speak of the rise of an era of post-truth
politics.
Post-truth is, however, a rather unspecific and polite term that fails
to point
out that the questioning of expertise aims at the advancement of lies
and
far-right ideology. Donald Trump has perfected the practice of
declaring any
expertise that questions him to be invalid and false. Figure 1 shows
an
example.
Figure 1: A tweet by Donald Trump about the mainstream media. Source: https://twitter.com/realdonaldtrump/status/832708293516632065
In the
tweet shown
in Figure 1, Donald Trump characterises certain mainstream media (New
York Times, ABC, CBS, CNN, NBC) that
often report critically about him as “the fake news media”. He thereby
identifies himself as the ultimate speaker and representative of the
American
people and implies that criticism of him is anti-American and directed
against
Americans. Critics of Trump are presented as “the enemy of the
American
people”. Driven by ideology, irrationality, and emotions, Trump and
his
followers imagine any criticism and facts not fitting their ideology
as
inventions. They only believe things that fit into their ideology to
be true.
Such a demagogic politics aims at radicalising followers and their
hatred of
identified enemies. It has dangerous, anti-democratic potentials
because
stoking hatred can easily spill over into violence.
A comparison of critical theories of fascism and authoritarianism shows
that there are four elements of right-wing authoritarian ideology,
practices,
and movements (Fuchs 2018; 2020b):
authoritarian
leadership, nationalism, the friend/enemy-scheme, and militant
patriarchy. Figure 2 visualises the interaction of these four
dimensions.
Right-wing authoritarianism has an ideological role. By fetishizing
the
illusionary collective of the nation, right-wing authoritarianism
distracts
attention from actual class conflicts and class structures. Fascism is
a
movement that uses terror as its means for advancing capitalism,
authoritarianism, nationalism, division, militancy, and patriarchy.
Figure 2: A model of right-wing authoritarianism (Fuchs
2018)
Roy identifies all four features of this model as key dimensions of fascism.
The “cult of Superman” is a central feature of fascism (Roy 1938, 40): “A Mussolini or Hitler is the personification of the cult of superman” (1938, 53). In fascism, “the State is everything and the individual citizen has no right to exist except as pawn of the absolute power which may gamble away his life whenever it pleases” (53).
Authoritarianism
uses a
“mass psychology dominated by the fear of freedom” (2006/1945,
13); “The fear of freedom created Fascism in Europe” (2006/1945,
15). The “flight from freedom […] is the basic social and cultural
asset of
Fascism” (23). This flight favours the belief
in the
need for top-down leadership and a Führer. When speaking of the flight
from
freedom it is evident that Roy (2006/1945) was
influenced by Erich Fromm’s (1969/1941) book Escape from Freedom, published
in 1941.
Fromm in this book analyses the rise of fascism in Europe: “The giant
forces in
society and the danger for man’s survival have increased […], and hence
man’s
tendency to escape from freedom” (1969/1941, xiii).
Roy does not explicitly
acknowledge
the connection to Fromm’s works. He does not cite or mention Escape
from Freedom or Fromm. Fromm
himself also became aware of Roy’s work. In his book The Sane Society, Fromm (2002/1956, 55)
describes Roy’s book Reason,
Romanticism
and Revolution as a “thorough and brilliant analysis”. Roy’s
journal The Radical Humanist
published articles
by Erich Fromm (Manjapra 2010, 160-161).
For Roy, nationalism is an ideology that fetishizes the nation. He therefore speaks of “national jingoism” (1938, 89). As a humanist, he politically despised any form of nationalism and argued that nationalism is an element of fascism: “Fascism is nationalism inspired by revivalist ideals” (1938, 40); “The essence of nationalism is to place the interests of one’s own country above the interests of the world” (1942, 7); “There is a spiritual affinity between nationalism and Fascism, the latter being only the most extravagant and aggressive form of the former” (1942, 22-23). Roy argues that Marxism is interested in social problems and conflicts while nationalism “has no reference to social problems” (2006/1945, 85). Nationalism demands the sacrifice of the individual to the nation. “The essence of Nationalism, the denial of the very existence of the individual, manifests itself fully in Fascism” (2006/1945, 29). Roy sees nationalism as a metaphysical and irrational ideology that fetishizes the nation:
Nazism
and Fascism are condemned as
totalitarian because they deny the sovereignty of the individual; they
do not
give the individual any place in society except as a cog in a vast
machinery
with a collective ego. […] Nationalism, by its internal logic, cannot
but be
totalitarian, because it also postulates a collective ego – the
nation. It is a
metaphysical concept; yet, human beings, of flesh and blood, must
sacrifice
everything to make the nation great and glorious. That is the essence
of
Nationalism. That is, to sacrifice a reality at the altar of a
fiction, of an
illusion (Roy 1960/1947, 110-111).
There are parallels of Roy’s critical theories of nationalism in the works of Rosa Luxemburg and Eric J. Hobsbawm (see Fuchs 2020b). Luxemburg and Hobsbawm, like Roy, stress the illusionary and fictive character of nationalist ideology. Luxemburg (1976/1909, 135) writes that nationalists see the nation as “a homogeneous social and political entity”, remarking that the nation is a “misty veil” concealing the “definite historical content” of class society (135). For Hobsbawm (1983a; 1983b; 1992), nationalism is an invented, which means fabricated and therefore illusionary, tradition that serves the interests of the capitalist class.
Roy (2006/1945, 85) argues that anti-colonial and anti-imperialist struggles that are nationalist in character are “pseudo-Marxist”:
The pseudo-Marxist theory of anti-Imperialism […] panders to the base sentiment of race hatred, and consequently plays into the hands of social reaction. The doctrine of united anti-Imperialist Front divorces political practice from the context of social conflicts, and making it an expression of racial animosity, helps the upper-class minority to use the people as a pawn in the game of power-politics. Providing nationalist power-politics with a pseudo-theoretical foundation, anti-Imperialism helps Nationalism to hide its reactionary social purpose. The misalliance with Nationalism compels Marxism to betray itself (2006/1945, 84-85).
The friend/enemy-scheme is the ideological construction of enemies who are blamed for society’s problems. Racism, anti-Semitism, anti-socialism, and anti-Marxism are typical enemy constructions that can be found in fascist ideology. Roy argues that fascism is driven by “fanatical race hatred” (1938, 143) and “unscrupulous slander against the opponents, [… the] fanning of race prejudice” (1938, 89). Fascism wants to destroy Marxism (93). The “object of Fascism is the destruction of the weak and the triumph of the strong” (133).
Capitalism is a “violent form of capitalist domination” (1938, 38). Fascism implements “arbitrary power and unbounded will” (53): “The Fascist state is the instrument of the dictatorship of the bourgeoisie divested of the deceit of parliamentary democracy” (87). Fascism is a capitalist system that is based on rule of terror. Fascism is “avowedly imperialist” (148), which implies the use of violence and terror for the expansion of capitalist influence.
Roy’s understanding of fascism resonates with that of the Frankfurt School (Jani 2017). Like Roy, Adorno and Horkheimer identify four dimensions of fascism.
In respect to authoritarian leadership, Adorno argues that the fascist leader presents himself as a great little man, “a person who suggests both omnipotence and the idea that he is just one of the folks” (1951, 142). Collective narcissism is a psychological dimension of authoritarianism, because it results in the psychological “enlargement of the subject: by making the leader his ideal he loves himself, as it were, but gets rid of the stains of frustration and discontent which mar his picture of his own empirical self” (Adorno 1951, 140).
In the context of nationalism, Adorno argues that fascists need forms of repressive egalitarianism. Fascist demagogues make use of the logic of repressive egalitarianism: “They emphasize their being different from the outsider but play down such differences within their own group and tend to level out distinctive qualities among themselves with the exception of the hierarchical one” (Adorno 1991, 146). Nationalism is a form of repressive egalitarianism.
Adorno argues that fascists think and act based on the logic of the friend/enemy-scheme. The right-wing demagogue “cannot help feeling surrounded by traitors, and so continuously threatens to exterminate them” (1975, 78). According to Adorno, identification with the leader and hatred against the out-group allows emotional release (1975, 16-20). Such a release of aggression encourages “excess and violence” (1975, 17).
Adorno stresses that fascists see the military as the model for politics and society and soldiers as ideal individuals. They consider war, violence, weapons and guns as the best means of handling conflicts. The “model of the military officer” is “transferred to the realm of politics” (1975, 49). Love towards the leader is an “emotional compensation for the cold, self-alienated life of most people” (1975, 37). For fascists, survival, toughness, strength and the willingness to fight, lead and compete are moral norms. Any “reference to love is almost completely excluded”, and the “traditional role of the loving father” is replaced “by the negative one of threatening authority” (Adorno 1991, 137). Horkheimer (2004/1947, 14) points out that nationalism ends in terror: “The idea of the national community (Volksgemeinschaft) first, first set up as an idol, can eventually only be maintained by terror”.
This article engaged with foundations of M. N. Roy’s theory and compared his approach to the Frankfurt School. The first question it asked was: How can M. N. Roy’s radical, Marxist humanism inform the critical study of communication, culture, technology, the human being, fascism, and nationalism? We can summarise the main findings in respect to the themes of humanism, technology, culture/communication, and ideology:
·
For
Roy,
humanism is a romantic movement that stresses the transformative
capacity
of human beings so that they can collectively make their own history.
·
For
Roy,
humanism is a movement for economic, political and cultural democracy,
a
movement for a participatory democracy that is based on co-operatives
and
networks of local assemblies.
·
Although
Roy
appreciates Marx’s humanism, he argues that there is a fatalistic
tendency
in Marx’s works that sees history as being determined by dialectical
economic
laws, advances moral relativism, and ignores the importance of human
essence
for humanism and democracy. Roy’s interpretation was not able to take
into
account some of Marx’s important works, especially the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, where Marx engages with the
notions of human essence as social, creative, self-conscious,
productive beings
and capitalism/class society as alienation from the human essence in
order to
ground a humanist-communist philosophy and politics.
·
Roy
misinterprets
Marx’s use of Hegelian dialectics. For Marx, dialectics is not
simply an objective law but, in society, also operates at the level of
the
human subject and its social relations, which means that class
struggle is an
open, dialectical process that has the potential to change society’s
history.
There is a dialectic of the subjective dialectic and the objective
dialectic.
Class struggle as the making and unmaking of class relations between
the
exploited and the exploited is the subjective dimension of history. It
does not
make sense to oppose Marx the humanist and Marx the Hegelian. Marx’s
dialectic
is humanist and his humanism dialectical.
·
Engaging
and
updating the works of humanist socialists such as Roy reminds us that
democratic socialism is the strongest weapon against fascism,
nationalism, and
war.
·
Roy
opposed
Gandhi’s nationalism and his vision of an ethical capitalism. He
argues
that Gandhi’s politics of a simple life is a form of pessimistic
technological
determinism, opposed to industry and modern technologies and thereby
celebrating
poverty and toil, which support capitalist interests.
·
Roy
stresses
the dialectical character of modern technology; that is, its potential
to advance slavery and freedom. The actual effects of science and
technology
depend on human interests, social relations and human practices in
these
relations.
·
While
Gandhi
was an anti-modernist, Roy argues for an alternative,
socialist-humanist
modernity that shapes, creates and uses technologies in manners that
abolish
toil and advance freedom, democracy and sustainability.
·
Roy
advances
a materialist monist position, which states that the entire world is
material.
·
Roy
sees
the brain as humans’ key means of production and humans as thinking
beings
capable of conceptual, creative, anticipatory thought. What needs to
be added
to Roy’s approach is the crucial role of work and production in human
existence. Humans are thinking, creative, social, producing,
communicating
beings. Social production combines the work character of communication
and the
communicative character of work.
·
Roy
challenges
the assumption that culture and ideas are reducible to the economy.
·
Roy’s
critique
of economic determinism during his last, humanist phase of
intellectual development was partly also self-criticism of his earlier
thought
that, based on Plekhanov, saw productive forces and especially
geography as
determining society.
·
Society
only
exists in and through humans’ social relations. Culture as the
production
and circulation of ideas and meanings takes place within the ensemble
of social
relations that constitutes the human subject.
·
Culture
cannot
be reduced to political economy; however, it is also not fully
independent but grounded in the economy, and at the same time
relatively autonomous.
Ideas and culture cannot be read off the mode of production. We can
learn from
Roy that a mode of production influences but does not determine forms
of
culture.
·
In
the
communication process, humans establish relations between their minds
and
thereby between individuals that constitute, produce, and reproduce
the social
world. They produce and reproduce social relations.
·
Roy
argues
that utilitarian liberalism created a negative dialectic of the
Enlightenment. Liberal individualism and atomism, expressing itself as
the
exploitation of wage-workers, the fetishization of private property,
capital
accumulation, cut-throat competition, and the logic of the
accumulation of
capital in the economy and of power in the state-system, has
backfired. The social
void it created has been filled with movements for repressive
collectivism,
namely fascism and Stalinism. Whereas liberal individualism fetishizes
the
individual at the expense of social freedom, fascism and Stalinism
fetishize
the collectives of the nation and the state at the expense of
individual
freedom.
·
Roy
identifies
four key elements of fascism: authoritarian leadership, nationalism,
the friend/enemy-scheme, and militarism. He opposes any form of
nationalism
because he sees nationalism as the irrational ideological foundation
of
fascism. Roy stresses that fascism is a violent and terroristic form
of
capitalism.
The second question that this article asked was: What commonalities
are there
between Roy’s approach and the critical theory of the Frankfurt
School? We can
summarise the main findings:
·
There are strong parallels between Roy’s and
Herbert Marcuse’s analysis of modern technology. Like Roy, Marcuse
rejects
anti-technological ideology that celebrates toil; Marcuse, like Roy,
identifies
both emancipatory and repressive potentials of modern technology and
argues
that the actual character and impact of technology depends on broader
societal
contexts, interests and struggles; Marcuse,
like
Roy, argues for a socialist modernity where technology is shaped and
used
in manners that overcome toil and advance freedom, and technology is
governed
in a democratic manner.
·
Roy
was
critical of positivism. His critique of the fetishism of mathematics
and
calculation resonates with the approaches of Georg Lukács, Theodor W.
Adorno,
Max Horkheimer, Friedrich Pollock, Alfred Sohn-Rethel, and Jürgen
Habermas, who
criticised positivism for lacking an understanding of the qualitative
and
dialectical character of the world.
·
There
are
parallels between Roy’s analysis of how liberalism turned against
itself
into fascism and Stalinism and Horkheimer/Adorno’s Dialectic of Enlightenment. Roy’s analysis of fascism is influenced
by Erich Fromm’s hypothesis of the escape from freedom. Roy, just like
the
Frankfurt School, sees authoritarian leadership, nationalism, the
friend/enemy-scheme, and militarism as key features of fascist
ideology and fascist
movements.
·
Roy,
like
Horkheimer, Adorno, and Marcuse, argues that Stalinism and fascism are
expressions of how the reason of Enlightenment, and liberalism that
questioned
religious and feudal rule, turned against Enlightenment values.
Capitalism
individualises and instrumentalizes humans, which undermines social
cohesion
and especially in crisis times calls forth reactionary forces that
fetishize
false and imaginary collectives such as the nation, race, and the
absolute
state.
·
Like
Marcuse,
Horkheimer and Adorno, Roy stresses that authoritarianism and fascism
try to treat humans like robots. This is the phenomenon of
instrumental reason
and technological rationality. Instrumental reason/technological
rationality
has four dimensions: technology as an instrument of domination,
capitalism as
social technology, ideology as the instrumentalization of
consciousness, and
technological determinism.
Both Roy and first-generation Frankfurt School authors such as Max
Horkheimer,
Theodor W. Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and Erich Fromm were inspired by
Marx and
humanist philosophy. The major difference between Roy and the Frankfurt
School
is that Roy analysed both Western and non-Western society, including
India and
China, based on Marxist humanism, whereas the Frankfurt School had to
limit its
analysis to Europe, the United States, and Russia. Marxist humanism is a
universal approach that is suited for the analysis of domination,
exploitation,
ideology, and social struggles in different parts of the world.
Roy’s approach shows that the claim that Marxian theory, socialism, and humanism are Western- or Euro-centric and therefore cultural imperialist approaches is erroneous. Whereas Dipesh Chakrabarty (2008, 4) argues that Roy was one of the “illustrious members” of the “modern Bengali educated middle classes” that “warmly embraced the themes of rationalism, science, equality, and human rights that the European Enlightenment promulgated”, Kris Manjapra (2010) argues in his book about Roy that the latter was not “entrapped in the ideologies attendant to global capital” (xviii), but an “anti-colonial cosmopolitan thinker” (xxi).
Robert Spencer (2017) maintains that post-colonial scholars often tar “all humanisms with the same brush” (121) and “champion difference at the expense of equality” and identity politics over class politics so that to “be a postcolonialist, it seems, is to leave one’s humanism at the door” (124). Spencer argues for a humanist postcolonialism that is “exercised above all not by crimes against hybridity but by crimes against humanity” (122), that stresses the human “capacity for self-creation” (128) and that speaks “the language of rights […] animated by the conviction that there are irreducible features of human life” (128) because “it is convinced that only by eradicating the most devastating forms of inhumanity will the human, with all its variability and unpredictableness, come into its own” (129). Humanism means “critical thinking + the ideal of solidarity” (152).
Marxist/socialist
humanism
allows us to approach the global world as a unity
of diverse tendencies. It is an approach that enables the analysis of
society in different contexts based on what Vivek Chibber calls the
two
universalisms, “the universal logic of capital (suitably defined) and
social
agents’ universal interest in their well-being, which impels them to
resist
capital’s expansionary drive” (2013, 291).
The first
universalism foregrounds the accumulation of economic, political and
cultural
power that in different contexts and on different levels of
organisation of
global society creates various inequalities. The second universalism
calls for
solidarity of the world’s oppressed and exploited in their struggles
for a
better world. One of the “recurring themes” in Roy’s works and thought
is “the
reading of underling unity out of apparent difference” (Manjapra
2010,
168).
Both in the West
and the
Global South, we today are experiencing a surge of new nationalisms and new authoritarianisms. Far-right movements
and new nationalisms are the “cicatrices and scars of a democracy […]
that
until today has still not lived up to its own concept” (Adorno
2019/1968, 18). They are the result of the negative
dialectic of neoliberal capitalism
and the new imperialism. The commodification of everything,
entrepreneurialism, privatisation, deregulation, financialisation,
capitalist
globalisation, the new imperialism, deindustrialisation, outsourcing,
precarisation
and the new individualism have backfired, extending and intensifying
inequalities and crisis tendencies, which have created a fertile
ground for new nationalisms,
right-wing extremism and new fascism.
Three of the main challenges and global problems that humanity faces
today are a) the threats of exploding inequalities, accelerating and
deepening
political-economic crises, fascism, war, violence and genocide posed
by the
rise of authoritarian capitalism and new nationalisms, b) the threat
posed to humans
and the environment by natural disasters, climate change and the
global
environmental crisis, and c) new forms of control and exploitation in
the
context of capitalist digital technologies, AI-based automation, and
algorithmic politics.
The political-economic crisis, the environmental crisis, and the digital
crisis have in common that they are crises that threaten fundamental
aspects of
human life, namely democracy, survival of the species and the planet,
and
self-fulfilment. They are crises of humanity. The three crises
together
radicalise the alienation of humans from nature, the economy,
political systems,
and culture to the point that the interaction of these crises can in
the future
result in a breakdown of humanity and the livelihood of future
generations. We
need radical alternatives. As Alderson and Spencer state, “The Left
[…]
requires a compelling vision of the future as more just, democratic, ecologically sustainable and subjectively
satisfying around which it will be possible to construct a viable
counter-hegemony” (2017, 218).
Radical
humanism is important today because it advances the counter-vision of
a humane
society against the dystopias the three crises could result in.
Radical
humanism can thereby inform social struggles. Radical humanism
struggles for
the strengthening of the political-economic commons (common control of
political and economic organisations), the natural commons (common
survival in
a natural environment that interacts with humans in sustainable
manners), and
the knowledge and digital commons (knowledge, culture, and digital
resources as
common goods).
In the age of new nationalisms and authoritarian capitalism, global
environmental crises, capitalist crisis, and the digital crisis,
socialist-humanist theories such as that of M. N. Roy can inspire
struggles for
a humanist and socialist society as antidotes to the acceleration and
deepening
of the three crises. In his Principles
of
Radical Democracy, Roy (1953, 52-62)
formulates 22
theses. The final one should be seen as the starting point for
contemporary
socialist, anti-fascist and anti-nationalist struggles:
Radicalism starts from the dictum that ‘man is the measure of everything’ (Protagoras) or ‘man is the root of mankind’ (Marx), and advocates reconstruction of the world as a commonwealth and fraternity of free […] [humans], by the collective endeavour of spiritually emancipated moral […] [humans] (Roy 1953, 62).
Adorno, Theodor W. 2019/1968. Aspekte des neuen
Rechtsradikalismus. Frankfurt
am Main: Suhrkamp.
Bastani, Aaron. 2019. Fully
Automated Luxury Communism: A Manifesto. London: Verso.
BBC. 2019. BBC News, 6
September
6 2019. Accessed 5 October. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=fSygWN-qMfY
(accessed on 5
October 2019)
Bloch, Ernst. 2019. Avicenna
and
the Aristotelean Left. New York: Columbia University Press.
Bose, Nirmal Kumar. 1948. Selections
from
Gandhi. Ahmedabad: Navajivan Publishing House.
Chibber, Vivek. 2013. Postcolonial Theory and the Specter of Capital. London: Verso.
Department for Business, Energy & Industrial Strategy. 2019. The
Grand Challenges. Accessed 7 October,
2019. https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/industrial-strategy-the-grand-challenges/industrial-strategy-the-grand-challenges#artificial-intelligence-and-data (version from 22 May 2019).
Fromm, Erich. 2002/1956. The Sane
Society. Abingdon: Routledge.
Fromm, Erich. 1969/1941. Escape From Freedom. New York: Avon Books.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1971. Knowledge
and Human Interest. Boston: Beacon Press.
Horkheimer, Max. 2004/1947. Eclipse of Reason. London: Continuum.
Horkheimer, Max. 1941. The End of Reason. Studies in Philosophy and Social Science 9 (3): 366-388.
Johnson, Boris. 2019. Wakefield Speech. 5 September. Accessed 5 October, 2019. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=G0x1k6p8PJU
Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and
Class Consciousness. London: Merlin.
Manjapra, Kris. 2010. M. N. Roy: Marxism and Colonial Cosmopolitanism. New Delhi: Routledge.
Marx, Karl. 1867. Capital Volume One. London: Penguin.
Marx, Karl. 1857. Grundrisse. London: Penguin.
Roy, M. N. 2006/1945. Problem
of Freedom. Calcutta:
Renaissance Publishers.
Roy, M. N. 1989. Reason, Romanticism and Revolution. Delhi: Ajanta Publications.
Roy, M. N. 1968. Men I Met. Bombay: Lalvani Publishing House.
Roy, M. N. 1960/1947. Beyond
Communism. Delhi: Ajanta Books.
Roy, M. N. 1953. New Humanism: A Manifesto. Calcutta: Renaissance Publishers. Second edition.
Roy, M. N. 1947a. Science and Philosophy. Calcutta: Renaissance Publishers.
Roy, M. N. 1946/1930. Revolution
and Counter-Revolution in China.
Calcutta: Renaissance Publishers.
Roy, M. N. 1943. The Communist International. Bombay: Radical Democratic Party Publications
Roy, M. N. 1942. Nationalism: An Antiquated Cult. Bombay: Radical Democratic Party
Roy, M. N. 1938. Fascism: Its Philosophy, Professions and Practice. Calcutta: D.M. Library.
Roy, M. N. 1923. India’s Problem and its Solution. Charleston: Nabu Press. Reprint.
Roy, M. N. 1922. India in Transition. Geneva: Edition de la Librairie J.B. Target.
Roy, M. N. 1920. Supplementary Theses on the National and Colonial Question. Presented at the Fourth Session of the Second Congress of the Communist International, July 25, 1920. Accessed 7 October, 2019. https://www.marxists.org/history/international/comintern/2nd-congress/ch04.htm
Roy, Samaren. 1997. M. N. Roy: A Political Biography. London: Sangam Books.
Roy, Samaren. 1987. M. N. Roy and Mahatma Gandhi. Columbia, MO: South Asia Books.
Williams, Alex and Nick Srnicek. 2013. #Accelerate: Manifesto for An Accelerationist Politics. Accessed 7 October, 2019. https://syntheticedifice.files.wordpress.com/2013/06/accelerate.pdf
Williams, Raymond. 2003/1974. Television: Technology and Cultural Form. London: Routledge.
Christian Fuchs
Christian Fuchs is a critical theorist and the co-editor of tripleC: Communication, Capitalism & Critique. http://fuchs.uti.at, http://www.triple-c.at, @fuchschristian
[1] Data
source:
https://scholar.google.com/, accessed on 12 September
2019.
[2] https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=GGgiGtJk7MA, accessed on 13 September
2019.